Argumenty bioetyki 2012
wykład 15
KLONOWANIE W CELACH
BADAWCZYCH
[źródła zarodkowych komórek
macierzystych]
• - zarodki pozostałe po kuracji in vitro
• - zarodki utworzone techniką in vitro
specjalnie w celach badawczych
• - zarodki utworzone w celach badawczych
metodą klonowania terapeutycznego
(SCNT), tj. przez transfer jądra ludzkiej
komórki somatycznej do ludzkiej komórki
jajowej
• - zarodki utworzone w celach badawczych
przez transfer jądra ludzkiej komórki
somatycznej do zwierzęcej komórki jajowej
• Devolder, Katrien, "Cloning", The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(Fall 2010 Edition), Edward N.
Zalta (ed.), URL =
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fal
• President's Council on Bioethics
(PCBE) (2002), Human Cloning and
Human Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry.
Washington D.C.: PCBE.
• Hansen, J.E. (2002) “Embryonic stem cell production
through therapeutic cloning has fewer ethical
problems than stem cell harvest from surplus IVF
embryos”, Journal of Medical Ethics, 28(2): 86–8.
• Hurlbut 2005 - William B. Hurlbut, “Patenting
humans: clones, chimeras, and biological artifacts”.
Science and Engineering Ethics (2005) 11, 21-29
• Hyun & Jung 2006 - Insoo Hyun and Kyu Won Jung,
“Human Research Cloning, Embryos, and Embryo-
Like Artifacts,” Hastings Center Report 36, no. 5
(2006): 34-41.
• McHugh, P.R. (2004) “Zygote and ‘clonote’—the
ethical use of embryonic stem cells”, New England
Journal of Medicine, 351(3): 209–11.
klonowanie - znaczenia
stworzenie genetycznej kopii sekwencji
NA lub całego genomu organizmu
przeniesienie jądra komórki
somatycznej (do opróżnionej z jądra
komórki jajowej) - somatic cell
nuclear transfer (SCNT)
klonowanie terapeutyczne (w
celach badawczych)
klonowanie reprodukcyjne
PCBE 2002 – medyczne cele
klonowania
• 1. Klonowanie w celu lepszego
zrozumienia ludzkiej choroby
• 2. Klonowanie w celu wynajdywania
nowych terapii ludzkich chorób
• 3. Klonowanie w celu wytwarzania
tkanek do przeszczepów nie
odrzucanych przez system
odpornościowy
• 4. Klonowanie wspomagające terapię
genową
klonowanie terapeutyczne –
argumenty przeciw
• szkody wyrządzane klonowanym
zarodkom
• szkody wyrządzane dawczyniom
oocytów
• szkody wyrządzane społeczeństwu
stanowiska w sprawie
etycznej oceny klonowania
• I. klonowanie terapeutyczne i tworzenie zarodków in
vitro w celu badawczym to praktyki etycznie
równorzędne, a mianowicie
A. równie dopuszczalne
[B. równie niedopuszczalne]
• II. klonowanie terapeutyczne jest etycznie bardziej
kontrowersyjne niż tworzenie „badawczych”
zarodków in vitro (ze względu na niebezpieczeństwa
równi pochyłej)
• III. klonowanie terapeutyczne jest etycznie mniej
kontrowersyjne niż tworzenie „badawczych”
zarodków in vitro (ze względu na niższy status
sklonowanych zarodków)
ad III. zarodek sklonowany a
zarodek zapłodniony
• Hansen, J.E. (2002) “Embryonic stem cell production
through therapeutic cloning has fewer ethical
problems than stem cell harvest from surplus IVF
embryos”, Journal of Medical Ethics, 28(2): 86–8.
• Hurlbut 2005 - William B. Hurlbut, “Patenting
humans: clones, chimeras, and biological artifacts”.
Science and Engineering Ethics (2005) 11, 21-29
• Hyun & Jung 2006 - Insoo Hyun and Kyu Won Jung,
“Human Research Cloning, Embryos, and Embryo-
Like Artifacts,” Hastings Center Report 36, no. 5
(2006): 34-41.
• McHugh, P.R. (2004) “Zygote and ‘clonote’—the
ethical use of embryonic stem cells”, New England
Journal of Medicine, 351(3): 209–11.
Hansen 2002
• The genetic complement of the fertilised egg is a
unique result of a fusion of a sperm cell and an egg
cell, and this may naturally evolve into an embryo, a
fetus, and eventually an infant. This is not the case
with an enucleated egg cell that has been
transplanted with the nuclear material from a
somatic cell. Neither is the genetic content unique,
for it is identical with the nuclear donor; nor is it
occurring naturally, with a natural potential of
evolvement into an embryo. It is entirely artificial
and leads its life in the laboratory unless somebody
chooses to implant it into a susceptible female
uterus before it can develop to the blastocyst stage,
when stem cell harvest is possible. (s. 86)
brak niepowtarzalności
• in my opinion the entire argument of deriving human
uniqueness from genetic uniqueness is flawed since
identical twins have identical genomes but are
evidently separate individuals. However, if emphasis is
none the less placed on the uniqueness of the new
genetic complement (the nuclear genome) of a
fertilised egg the differences between a fertilised egg
and a transnuclear egg cell would be significant and
the transnuclear egg cell could not be considered a
human being even if a naturally fertilised egg cell were
to be so considered. The genome of the transnuclear
egg cell already exists in the cells of the donor of the
nucleus. So either one must give up the notion that
human individuality is related to genetic uniqueness or
accept that a transnuclear egg cell is not a human
individual. (s. 87)
brak naturalności
• While the concept of natural purpose may be
dubious— consider for instance that the great
majority of naturally fertilised eggs perish before
term—the purpose of a transnuclear egg cell is
clearly not defined by nature.10 Therefore, if
emphasis is placed on the natural purpose of a
fertilised egg to evolve into an embryo and
eventually a human being, the transnuclear egg
cell would fall outside the category of human
beings as there are no natural occurrences
whereby a transnuclear egg cell develops into a
fetus. As with all other artifacts, its purpose is
properly defined through human design. (s. 87)
McHugh 2004 – zarodki in
vitro i zarodki sklonowane
• I argue that this process of SCNT, by causing the
expression of an intrinsic potential for growth and
replication that is found in every somatic cell, can
extend and expand a donor’s cellular mass into
extracorporeal space, as any form of tissue culture
does. The stem cells that issued from the process
would, in this view, be licitly used as the donor
allowed. To specify this fundamental difference
between in vitro fertilization and SCNT, I suggested
that, since we call the first cell produced by
fertilization the zygote, we dub the combination of
nucleus and enucleated ovum that launches SCNT
the “clonote.” (McHugh 2004, s. 210)
Hurlbut 2005
• The crucial principle in all such efforts, however, must be
the preemptive nature of the intervention, the intentional
construction of an entity that cannot be reasonably
designated a living being. The intervention that precludes
the possibility of human development would be undertaken
at a stage before the transition to organismal status and
thus no active potentiality, no human life in process would
be violated, mutilated or destroyed. If the artifact were
accorded a certain cautionary respect (as with all human
tissues) even though not the full protection of human life,
the consequences of such a program would not compromise
any moral principle. Just as we have learned that neither
genes, nor cells, nor even whole organs define the locus of
human moral standing, in this era of developmental biology
we will come to recognize that cells and tissues with ‘partial
developmental potential’ may be used for medical benefit
without a violation of human dignity. (Hurlbut 2005, s. 27-
28)
Hyun & Jung 2006
• Using this primate research as a point of reference,
we believe one can reasonably argue that the
squish enucleation process for creating human
SCNT blastocysts for stem cell research might very
well have the effect of simultaneously barring these
SCNT blastocysts from developing into a future
human life. For primates, unlike previously cloned
animal species, the same technology that makes
research cloning possible may also make primate
reproductive cloning impossible. Thus human
research cloning may soon emerge as scientific
reality while human reproductive cloning may
remain science fiction. (Hyun & Jung 2006, s. 38)