Philosophical Strategies [Althusser And Spinoza]

background image

Peter Thomas
Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza

Introduction

1

Louis Althusser is chiey remembered today, when

he is remembered at all, as the progenitor and

leading exponent of structuralist Marxism, a curious

hybrid which ourished on the left bank of the

Seine in the 1960s and later enjoyed the status of an

exotic import in the left-wing Anglophone academy

in the late 1960s and early 1970s. Structuralist

Marxism was regarded as the convergence of two

independent ‘conjunctures’: on the one hand, the

‘structuralist’ movement, whose emergence in post-

Resistan ce French in tellectual life seemed to

offer the possibility of a powerfully unifying dis-

course across the ossiŽed boundaries of the human

and social sciences; and on the other, those currents

within Western Marxism which were attempting to

renew Marxist theory in the space opened up by the

partial thaw of Stalinism following Khrushchev’s

Historical Materialism, volume 10:3 (71–113)
© Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2002
Also available online –

www.brill.nl

1

I would like to thank Gary Maclennan, Paul Jones, Dan O’Neill, Martin Thomas,

Murray Kane, Melissa White, Ben Jones, Daniel Bensaïd, John Game and Sebastian
Budgen for encouraging remarks and suggestions on a previous version of this paper.
Ted Stolze, Gregory Elliott, Geoff Goshgarian, André Tosel and Warren Montag did
not allow positive references to their own work to blind them to the deŽciencies
of mine.

background image

‘secret speech’ of 1956. Structuralism had been hailed initially as a decisive

intellectual advance of potentially epochal dimensions (witness the famous

closing lines of Foucault’s The Order of Things). But it was almost as quickly
relegated to the dustbin of history, granted a lingering half-life as a pedagogical

prop used in introducing students to post-structuralism. A similar fate awaited

the work of Louis Althusser. The advent of Althusser’s ‘structuralist’ reading

of Marx and of some of the central categories of Marxist theory seemed, for

some at least, the necessary correlate at the level of high theory of the more

general structure of feeling and revolutionary optimism now referred to by

the title of ‘The Sixties’. But the Althusserian moment was soon eclipsed by

a combination of international political events, tragedy in the personal life of

its protagonist, and most importantly, a radical change in intellectual fashion.

As Gregory Elliott notes,

The alliance Althusser had sought in the early 1960s between Marxism and

avant-garde French theory unravelled after 1968 as the philosophies of desire

and power tributary to May drove high structuralism from the seminar

room. Althusserianism was thus doubly compromised – as a Marxism and

as a structuralism.

2

Having ‘hitched [his] Marxism to structuralism’s rising star’, it seemed that

Althusser’s thought was condemned to follow it into the archive of failed

projects.

3

Althusserianism passed into the memories (sometimes with fond-

ness, more often, perhaps, with regret) of those Communists and New-Leftist

intellectuals who had ocked to its banner in its heyday, while some of

Althusser’s central texts, particularly the celebrated ‘Ideology and Ideological

State Apparatuses: Notes Towards an Investigation’, subsequently became

foundational texts in the post-1960s reformulation of the social sciences and

cultural studies.

4

There was at least one Marxist theorist, however, for whom the equation

of the Althusserian tendency with structuralism was far from self-evident:

Louis Althusser himself. In his Éléments d’Autocritique of 1974 (published in
English in 1976 in the volume Essays in Self-Criticism), Althusser explicitly

72 • Peter Thomas

2

Elliott 1987, p. 282.

3

Elliott 1987, p. 283.

4

The most comprehensive accounts of the fate of Althusser’s work can be found

in Kaplan and Sprinker 1993 and Elliott 1994.

background image

denied that he and his co-workers had been structuralists, and, in their defence,

offered an alternative intellectual afŽliation. He argued:

If we never were structuralists, we can now explain why: why we seemed

to be, even though we were not, why there came about this strange mis-

understanding on the basis of which books were written. We were guilty

of an equally powerful and compromising passion: we were Spinozists . . . with

very few exceptions our blessed critics, imbued with conviction and swayed

by fashion, never suspected any of this. They took the easy road: it was so

simple to join the crowd and shout ‘structuralism’! Structuralism was all

the rage, and you did not have to read about it in books to be able to talk

about it. But you have to read Spinoza and know that he exists: that he still

exists today. To recognize him, you must at least have heard of him.

5

Gregory Elliott has voiced an obvious objection to this line of defence:

‘Admission of Spinozism does not automatically compel acquittal on the

count of structuralism, and it had been apparent some time before Althusser’s

confession’.

6

Some critics, already enraged by the theoretical anti-humanism

of Althusser’s structuralist Marxism, in which human agency was reduced

to mere Träger of the relations of production, seemed to regard Althusser’s
declared admiration for one of the most rigorous determinists of the modern

philosophical tradition as merely adding insult to injury. So rather than

closing the case against Louis Althusser, his confession of Spinozism instead

resulted in his Marxism becoming doubly condemned – as both a struc-

turalism and as a Spinozism.

Yet, as Montag has noted, it is questionable whether this pronouncement

was an accurate remembrance of the forces which shaped the early Althusserian

project (speciŽcally, the texts For Marx and Reading Capital), or was rather,
‘nothing more than a retrospective construction, the very condition of which

was a renaissance in French Spinoza studies that took place at the end of the

sixties’.

7

Montag points to the lack of any systematic and textually explicit

studies of Spinoza by Althusser and his colleagues in this period, arguing

that, even if it is true that the Althusserian school developed in a Spinozistic

environment, ‘they nevertheless did not produce any sustained work on

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 73

5

Althusser 1976, p. 132.

6

Elliott 1987, p. 183.

7

Montag 1998, pp. xi–xii.

background image

Spinoza, certainly nothing resembling their “readings” of other philosophers’.

8

Their interest in Spinoza remained vague and indeterminate during the period

when the Althusserian paradigm’s central features were elaborated, and it

was only later, in very different political and intellectual circumstances, that

it solidiŽed into a deŽnite line of research. Even then, it was not Althusser

who produced an extended study of Spinoza’s relevance to Marxism (his

published comments are limited to a chapter in Essays in Self-Criticism, and

several confessional passages from his autobiographical writings), but some

of his former students and colleagues (primarily, Balibar and Macherey), as

their own development led them in directions not entirely compatible with

the austere theoreticism for which the Althusserian moment is remembered.

Considerations on Western Marxism

Nevertheless, as Montag further notes, ‘Althusser’s assertion in Elements of

Self-Criticism that he, Balibar and Macherey “were Spinozists”, [was taken by
Perry Anderson] as conŽrmation of his worst suspicions concerning Althusser’s

reliance on pre-Marxist thought’.

9

Anderson was one of Althusser’s few,

blessed critics who had indeed heard of Spinoza. In fact, in the epigraphs to

his celebrated and widely inuential study, Considerations on Western Marxism,
Anderson gave pride of place to the following juxtaposition of the views of

Lenin and Spinoza on the relationship of philosophy to political practice.

Correct revolutionary theory assumes Žnal shape only in close connection

with the practical activity of a truly mass and truly revolutionary movement.

LENIN

The multitude, and those of like passions with the multitude, I should

ask not to read my book; nay, I would rather that they should utterly neglect

it, than that they should misinterpret it after their wont. SPINOZA

10

74 • Peter Thomas

8

Montag 1998, p. xi. Montag’s comments should be understood as referring to

the exoteric doctrines of Althusser and his circle in this period (though he perhaps
underestimates the extent of the Spinozistic elements to be found even in these,
particularly Reading Capital). Within the general intellectual environment of this
group, Spinoza was an abiding and constant presence. Thanks are due to Gregory
Elliott for stressing this point.

9

Montag 1998, p. xi.

10

Anderson 1976, p. ix. The quotation from Lenin is from Left-Wing Communism –

An Infantile Disorder (Lenin 1950, p. 15); Spinoza’s is from the preface to the Tractatus
Theologico-Politicus
(Spinoza 1951, p. 11). Several features should be briey noted here

background image

As the argument of Considerations on Western Marxism made clear, Spinoza’s
statement was considered by Anderson to be a precursor of the esotericism,

élitism and removal from politics which he nominated as some of the deŽning

co-ordinates of Western Marxism as a whole. As he noted, without the slight-

est hint of irony, the ‘very surplus [of Western Marxist theorists’ works]

above the necessary minimum quotient of verbal complexity was the sign

of its divorce from any popular practice’.

11

The fundamental cause of this

development, Anderson argued, had been the experience of Stalinism. With

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 75

as a corrective to Anderson’s implicit suggestion of Spinoza’s élitism and removal
from politics. First, the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (TTP) was a work dedicated to
combating the intellectual foundations of superstition (the dominant ideological
formation of Spinoza’s time and place, the Dutch Republic of the 1660s) by means of
a scrupulous examination of the meaning and history of scripture. Furthermore,
it was an intervention into a hostile political and theological climate (as Spinoza,
excommunicated from Amsterdam’s Jewish community and already regarded with
suspicion by the ‘liberal’ Christianity of the Netherlands, knew only too well), one
rapidly moving to the Right as the Calvinist orthodoxy and the House of Orange
mobilised a discontented populace against the republic of the liberal mercantile
bourgeoisie. Spinoza’s request that ‘those of like passions with the multitude’ should
not read his book (i.e. the multitude in the Netherlands in the 1660s, who were
rallying to the banner of reaction and religious orthodoxy) was less an élitist separa-
tion of intellectuals from ‘the masses’ than prudent advice to the orthodox among
his contemporaries that they were bound to be offended by his demolition of the
misinterpretations upon which their prejudices and régime of mystiŽcation were
founded. (SigniŽcantly, despite, or perhaps because of, this ‘conjunctural’ role of the
multitude, the political theory of both the TTP and the later, post-restoration Tractatus
Politicus
are suffused with an awareness that it is the power and imagination of
the multitude which determine the course of political events). Finally, the TTP was
also designed, in part, as a secular resolution to the ongoing Averroist controversy
concerning the proper relation between philosophy and theology which had marked
the emergence of modern Europe from the theocracy of the Middle Ages. Spinoza
was appealing to an audience of fellow philosophers, or potential philosophers, to
resolve this debate Žnally in the interests of the autonomy of reason, in much the
same way as Lenin’s Left-Wing Communism was, in part, an appeal to fellow communists
to adopt a political outlook appropriate to their own concrete political conditions.
The passage in full reads as follows: ‘To the rest of mankind I care not to commend
my treatise, for I cannot expect that it contains anything to please them: I know
how deeply rooted are the prejudices embraced under the name of religion; I am
aware that in the mind of the masses superstition is no less deeply rooted than fear;
I recognise that their constancy is mere obstinacy, and that they are led to praise
or blame by impulse rather then reason. Therefore the multitude, and those of
like passions with the multitude, I ask not to read my book; nay, I would rather that
they should utterly neglect it, than that they should misinterpret it after their wont.
They would gain no good themselves, and might prove a stumbling block to others,
whose philosophy is hampered by the belief that Reason is a mere handmaid to
Theology, and whom I seek in this work especially to beneŽt’ (Spinoza 1951, p. 11).
For an excellent discussion of these and related themes, see Tosel 1997, particularly
pp. 150–6.

11

Anderson 1976, p. 54.

background image

‘the failure of proletarian revolutions in the advanced zones of European

capitalism after the First World War’, the rise of a bureaucratic ruling élite

in the Soviet Union and the Stalinisation of the Comintern, the connection

of Marxist theory and revolutionary working-class practice, which had

characterised historical materialism in its classical phase, was severed.

12

Thereafter, Western Marxist theorists led a shadowy half-life on the edge of

the Communist parties, bullied, cajoled and disciplined by the apparatus

if they chose to remain within them (often resulting in a self-imposed

censorship and increasingly cryptic language), marginalised and isolated

from contact with the organisations of the working class if they opted for the

role of fellow-traveller or ‘friendly’ critic. Under these conditions, Western

Marxism began increasingly to turn towards both pre- and non-Marxist

philosophy, a shift symptomatic of these theorists’ distance from tasks of

direct political organisation (giving their thought an increasingly speculative

dimension, tending towards the history of philosophy) and working-class

culture (leading them to a closer relationship with contemporary bourgeois

culture and theory, rather than proletarian practice).

Anderson acknowledged that the turn to pre-Marxist philosophy, in par-

ticular, had Žlled a noticeable gap in the comprehensiveness of historical

materialism as an intellectual research programme. ‘Any creative development

of Marxist philosophy as such’, Anderson noted,

would inevitably have had to move through a reconsideration of the

complex cognitive history which Marx himself ignored or bypassed. The

existing starting-points within the work of Marx itself were too few and too

narrow for this not to be necessary.

13

This acknowledgement, however, was accompanied by a cautionary note:

At the same time, the dangers involved in a prolonged recourse to pre-

Marxist philosophical traditions need no emphasis: the overwhelming weight

of idealist or religious motifs within them is well enough known.

14

If the explication and supplementation of the works of Marx were required,

Anderson seemed to suggest, these resources should be drawn from the

76 • Peter Thomas

12

Anderson 1976, p. 92.

13

Anderson 1976, p. 61.

14

Ibid.

background image

experience of class struggle as it has unfolded since Capital – not from the
formulations and arguments of philosophers whose thought lay on the wrong

side of Marx’s ‘Copernican revolution’.

When he turned to an explicit consideration of Althusser’s Spinozism,

Anderson found it to be a particular manifestation, if not the example par

excellence, of this general Western Marxism tendency of turning to pre-Marxist

philosophy in order ‘to legitimate, explicate or supplement the philosophy

of Marx himself’.

15

‘Less philologically explicit’ than other Western Marxist

attempts to read Marx in relation to Hegel, Kant etc., Anderson argued that

Althusser’s engagement with Spinoza was nevertheless ‘substantively the

most sweeping retroactive assimilation of all of a pre-Marxist philosophy into

Marxism’, ‘the most ambitious attempt to construct a prior philosophical

descent for Marx, and to develop abruptly new theoretical directions for

contemporary Marxism from it’.

16

In order to support this judgement, Anderson had carefully noted the

scattered and often elliptical references to Spinoza in For Marx and Reading

Capital, which he here systematised and whose signiŽcance he briey assessed.
The inuence of Spinoza on Althusser was found to be pervasive. Anderson

went so far as to argue that ‘nearly all the novel concepts and accents of

Althusser’s Marxism, apart from those imported from contemporary disci-

plines, were in fact directly drawn from Spinoza’.

17

Despite the disclaimer

that Althusser had also been inuenced by contemporaneous currents in

non-Marxist philosophy and other academic disciplines (those thinkers and

thought-forms most often noted by Althusser’s critics and expositors, such

as Bachelard and developments in epistemology and the philosophy of

science, Lacan’s re-reading of Freud and psychoanalysis, and, of course, Lévi-

Strauss and the high-structuralist tradition itself), the Spinozistic inuences

on Althusser, outlined by Anderson, were, in fact, so comprehensive as to

leave very little in the Althusserian system which was not ‘directly drawn’,

‘taken straight’, ‘faithfully derived’ from Spinoza. Anderson nominated the

six following correspondences between the thought of Althusser and Spinoza:

18

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 77

15

Anderson 1976, p. 59.

16

Anderson 1976, pp. 64–5.

17

Anderson 1976, p. 64.

18

The list of correspondences and supporting references occurs on pp. 64–5.

Unfortunately, space will not permit the full examination and explication which they

background image

First, Anderson argued that Althusser’s ‘categorical distinction between

“objects of knowledge” and “real objects” was taken straight from Spinoza’s

famous separation of idea and ideatum’.

19

Second, ‘the Althusserian “general essence of production”, common to both

thought and reality’, was regarded as ‘none other than a translation of the

Spinozan maxim ordo et connexio idearum rerum idem est, ac ordo et connexio

rerum (“The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and
connection of things”)’.

20

Third, Anderson detected in Althusser’s controversial thesis of the self-

validating procedures of theoretical practice and consequent ‘radical elimi-

nation of the philosophical problem of the guarantees of knowledge or truth’

the inuence of ‘Spinoza’s dictum veritas norma sui et falsi’.

21

78 • Peter Thomas

deserve. Passages additional to those offered by Anderson will also be noted for the
interested reader. I have adopted the standard references for passages from the Ethics:
D = DeŽnition, P = Proposition, Sch = Scholium, App = Appendix.

19

The relevant passages noted by Anderson are: Althusser and Balibar 1970, p. 40;

Spinoza 1985, p. 12. Also important are EIIP6, EIIP7Sch.

20

Althusser 1977, p. 169; Althusser and Balibar 1970, p. 216; EIIP7Sch. Althusser ’s

account of the process of abstraction in Marx in fact departs from Spinoza’s empha-
sis upon the symmetry of the orders within the attributes. For Althusser, in Reading
Capital
, ‘“thought” is a peculiar real system, established on and articulated to the
real world of a given historical society’ (p. 42), but this articulation is one of uneven-
ness rather than identity. SigniŽcantly, Althusser maintains that ‘Marx goes even
further [than Spinoza] and shows that this distinction [between idea and ideatum/
thought-concrete and real-concrete] involves not only these two objects, but also their
peculiar production processes’ (p. 41). See, in particular, the following argument:
‘While the production process of a given real object, a given real-concrete totality (e.g.,
a given historical nation) takes place entirely in the real and is carried out according
to the real order of real genesis (the order of succession of the moments of historical
genesis), the production process of the object of knowledge takes place entirely in
knowledge and is carried out according to a different order, in which the thought
categories which “reproduce” the real categories do not occupy the same place as they
do in the order of real historical genesis, but quite different places assigned them by
their function in the production process of the object of knowledge’ (p. 41) (Italics
in original; underlining mine). This divergence is important for two reasons, which
will become clearer later in this argument. First, it refutes Anderson’s thesis of the
identity of the concepts: Althusser himself points out that there is a signiŽcant
difference between his (and Marx’s) concept and that of Spinoza. Second, because
Althusser clearly posits that Marx himself had already taken over concepts from
Spinoza and further developed them (even if unconsciously), it refutes Anderson’s
claim that Althusser’s deployment of Spinozistic themes was a novel and unwar-
ranted development in Marxist theory.

21

Althusser and Balibar 1970, pp. 59–60, EIIP43Sch. Also relevant are Spinoza 1985,

pp. 18–19, and the deŽnition of an adequate idea in EIIDiv.

background image

Fourth, ‘the central concept of ‘structural causality’ of a mode of produc-

tion in Reading Capital’ was judged to be ‘a secularized version of Spinoza’s
conception of God as a causa immanens’.

22

Fifth, Anderson argued that ‘Althusser’s passionate attack on the ideolog-

ical illusions of immediate experience as opposed to the scientiŽc knowledge

proper to theory alone, and on all notions of men or classes as conscious

subjects of history, instead of as involuntary “supports” of social relations,

was an exact reproduction of Spinoza’s denunciation of experientia vaga
as the source of all error, and his remorseless insistence that the archetypal

delusion was men’s belief that they were in any way free in their volition,

when in fact they were permanently governed by laws of which they were

unconscious’.

23

Sixth, and Žnally, Anderson argued that the ‘implacable determinism’,

which had led Spinoza to argue that ‘Those who believe that a people, or

men divided over public business, can be induced to live by reason alone,

are dreaming of the poet’s golden age or a fairy tale’, had been adapted by

Althusser’s infamous thesis that ideology is ‘the very element and atmosphere

indispensable [to human societies’] historical respiration and life’.

24

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 79

22

Althusser and Balibar 1970, pp. 187–9; EIP18.

23

Althusser 1977, pp. 232–5; Althusser and Balibar 1970, p. 180; EIIP35. See also

Spinoza’s discussion of the consequences of human ignorance of the causes of things
in EIApp.

24

Althusser 1977, p. 232. Anderson incorrectly attributed the quote from Spinoza

to the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, rather than to the post-restoration Tractatus Politicus.
His failure to contextualise this argument politically and historically allowed him
to misrepresent it as a deep pessimism, rather than as an expression of the political
realism adopted by Spinoza in a period of reaction. After the fall of the Dutch repub-
lic, Spinoza composed the Tractatus Politicus as an attempt to analyse the different
forms of government, not as political theorists argued they ought to be, but as they
had been realised in concrete forms in human history. The passage in full reads
as follows: ‘We showed [in the Ethics] that reason can, indeed, do much to restrain
and moderate the passions, but we saw at the same time, that the road, which
reason herself points out, is very steep; so that such as persuade themselves, that the
multitude or men distracted by politics can ever be induced to live according to the
bare dictate of reason, must be dreaming of the poetic golden age, or of a stage-play’
(Spinoza 1951, p. 289). A full exposition of this passage, and a demonstration that
it in fact involves a valorisation of the imagination of the multitude rather than
a rationalist dismissal of it, would need to refer to at least the following passages:
the origin of inadequate ideas in EIApp, the three kinds of knowledge – imagination,
reason and intuitive knowledge – outlined in EIIP40Sch2, the deŽnitions of truth and
falsity in EIIP41 and EIIP35, the deŽnition of ‘the object of the idea constituting the
human mind’ as ‘the body’ in EIIP13 and the supporting proposition EIIP29Sch on

background image

Just as Althusser had attempted to read the ‘symptomatic silences’ of Marx’s

‘problematic’, it appeared that Anderson had attuned his ear to the faint

echoes which resonated throughout Althusser’s own work.

25

With the decline

of the popularity of the Althusserian paradigm in the English-speaking leftist

academy, which was well noticeable even before the publication of Considerations

on Western Marxism, and declining interest in Marxism in general, which

was soon to follow (particularly those ‘High Theoreticist’ variants which

claimed a privileged access to a ‘Truth’ denied to mere ‘lived experience’),

this assessment became for a long period the accepted account of the nature

and content of Althusser’s Spinozism.

Considerations on Western Marxism was one of the Žrst studies in Anglophone

Marxism to identify Althusser’s Spinozistic inspiration, a conclusion which

Anderson repeated in Arguments in English Marxism and in the editorial intro-
duction (ascribed to New Left Review, but presumably written, or contributed

to, by Anderson) to André Glucksmann’s ‘A Ventriloquist Structuralism’ in

the anthology Western Marxism: A Critical Reader.

26

It was, and to some extent

continues to be, widely inuential on subsequent studies of Althusser within

Anglophone Marxism. Critics such as, on the one hand, Steven Smith, and,

on the other, E.P. Thompson, Terry Eagleton and Ellen Meiksins Wood, have

either reproduced Anderson’s arguments almost verbatim with little or

no further commentary, as in the former case, or briey mentioned the

importance of Spinoza for Althusser in passing, as in the latter.

27

Gregory

Elliott’s The Detour of Theory contains some suggestive discussions of the
Spinoza/Althusser relationship and its relevance to historical materialism,

80 • Peter Thomas

the mind’s confused knowledge of the body, and, Žnally, Spinoza’s observation that
although it was ‘the object of the idea constituting the human mind’, ‘no one’ – least
of all political theorists – ‘has yet determined what the body can do’ in EIIIP2Sch.
The reader interested in the evolution of Spinoza’s political thought is referred to the
book-length studies of Negri’s The Savage Anomaly and Balibar’s Spinoza and Politics
and Warren Montag’s Masses, Bodies, Power: Spinoza and his Contemporaries. Montag
has also provided an excellent short and accessible summary of the main themes in
his Preface to Balibar’s Spinoza and Politics.

25

The Althusserian notion of symptomatic reading itself bears an important

relation to Spinoza’s proposals for the unmystiŽed interpretation of scripture in Chapter
7 of the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, pp. 98–119. For an extended discussion of this
theme, see Montag 1993.

26

Anderson 1980, p. 125; New Left Review 1977, p. 275.

27

Smith 1984, pp. 72–3; Thompson 1978, p. 201; Eagleton 1991, p. 146; Meiksins

Wood 1986, p. 18.

background image

but his assessment remains ambivalent with regard to the interpretation of

Considerations on Western Marxism. Two works stand out against the general

current of acceptance of Anderson’s judgement: Andrew Collier’s ScientiŽc

Realism and Socialist Thought provides, among other interesting insights

into the enduring relevance of the questions raised by Althusser, a novel

treatment of Spinoza’s theory of composite bodies in relation to the Althusserian

theory of structural causality. And Christopher Norris, in one of the longest

and most signiŽcant studies of Althusser’s afŽnities with Spinoza (Spinoza

and the Origins of Modern Critical Theory) provides a more sympathetic and
nuanced discussion.

28

Despite these exceptions, Anderson’s account of

Althusser’s Spinozism became, due to a combination of his pre-eminence

among Anglophone Marxists, the novelty of his study in its time and the

characteristic conŽdence of his presentation, an important pole of reference

for several generations of both theoretical and activist Marxists. The fact that

it assumed this importance, despite its brevity (scarcely two pages, and those

in a study whose main purpose was quite other than an examination of

Spinoza’s relation to Marxism), is an index of how totally marginal Spinoza

has been until recently not only to Marxism but to Anglophone intellectual

culture as a whole. The purpose of this study is to critically assess Anderson’s

judgement, in the hope that one of the obstacles which presently impedes

the more widespread engagement of Anglophone Marxism with the thought

of Spinoza will thereby be removed. It also attempts to offer an alternative

assessment of the nature of Althusser’s Spinozism, and in conclusion, to posit

some preliminary theses to be used in a future study of contemporary Marxist

Spinozisms.

Spinoza and pre-Althusserian Marxism

Recent research, however, has indicated that the three assumptions upon

which Anderson’s analysis rested – Spinoza’s externality to pre-Althusserian

Marxism, the notion that Althusser was offering Spinoza as a philosophical

ancestor for Marx, and that Althusser had directly transcribed certain cen-

tral propositions of Spinoza – are not as persuasive as was perhaps once

thought. Indeed, the last thirty years have witnessed a veritable renaissance

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 81

28

Collier 1989, particularly pp. 80–90; Norris 1991, particularly Chapter 1.

background image

in scholarship and interest in Spinoza, comparable to the Spinozism of

German Romanticism and its aftermath, which followed the Pantheismusstreit
produced by Jacobi’s disclosure in 1787 that Lessing had considered himself

a Spinozist. Beginning in France in the late 1960s, studies by Marxists such

as Macherey, Balibar, Tosel and Negri, and more recently, Montag, have been

central to the transformation of the received image of Spinoza as a god-

intoxicated pantheist.

29

In particular, these studies have made clear that

Anderson’s claim that Spinoza had been largely external to pre-Althusserian

Marxism can no longer be sustained, for two reasons. First, Marx himself had

read Spinoza passionately and had even gone so far as to transcribe passages

from Spinoza into his notebooks under the strange title ‘Spinoza’s Tractatus

Theologico Politicus by Karl Marx’. Anderson did, of course, acknowledge

this engagement, but immediately asserted that despite this, ‘there is little

sign that he was ever particularly inuenced by him. Only a handful of

references to Spinoza, of the most banal sort, can be found in Marx’s work’.

30

Yet, as Yirmiyahu Yovel’s treatment in Spinoza and Other Heretics has demon-

strated (signiŽcantly, because Yovel is not a Marxist seeking to justify a

Spinozist ‘deviation’), Marx’s engagement with Spinozistic themes extended

beyond his youth and explicit references and became an abiding inuence

on the works of his ‘maturity’.

31

Similarly, Anderson was incorrect to argue

that Althusser was the Žrst signiŽcant Marxist to be drawn to Spinoza, aside

from such Žgures as Plekhanov, Labriola and even Engels himself.

32

As Montag

notes,

82 • Peter Thomas

29

A review of these recent Marxist Spinozisms will appear in a future issue of

Historical Materialism.

30

Anderson 1976, p. 64. Among the less banal references by Marx is his ranking

of Spinoza as an ‘intensive philosopher ’, ‘a pure ideal ame of science’, and an
‘animating spirit of world-historical developments’ alongside Aristotle and Hegel
(Marx and Engels 1975, p. 496). Also important is Marx’s argument in his early Critique
of Hegel’s Doctrine of the State
that ‘democracy is the essence of all political constitutions,
socialised man as a particular political constitution; it is related to other forms of
constitution as a genus to its various species’ (Marx 1974, p. 88). This is a perspec-
tive which remains the foundation of Marx’s political views throughout his work,
nowhere more so than in Capital, and which bears an important resemblance to
Spinoza’s analysis of the foundation of the different forms of government in the
Tractatus Politicus. The point is not to play off one list of references against another.
Rather, it is that Anderson’s brusque dismissal on the basis of explicit references to
Spinoza in Marx’s major works was issued before a thorough study had been made
of both ‘exoteric’ and ‘esoteric’ Spinozism in Marx’s entire oeuvre.

31

Yovel 1989, Vol. 2.

32

As Montag correctly notes, Anderson followed Colletti (a continental point of

background image

a deŽnitive account of [the history of Marxist detours through Spinoza]

remains to be written. In each succeeding period of crisis within Marxism,

usually occasioned by a stabilization and expansion of capitalism after an

economic and/or political crisis that was hailed as ‘Žnal’, in the 1890s, the

1920s, the 1970s and 1980s, prominent Marxists, many of whom (from

Thalheimer to Negri) do not Žt the proŽle of the Western Marxist painted

by Anderson, turned to Spinoza’s philosophy.

33

Second, the presence of explicit references or not do not account for what

Pierre Macherey has referred to, in reference to Heidegger, Adorno and

Foucault, but undoubtedly with Spinoza in mind, as a thinker’s ‘philosophical

actuality’. Macherey has argued that

One can consider a philosophy to be living or present not only because

it constitutes a source of reference or an object of study and reection

but because its problems and some of its concepts, independently of

every explicit citation, nonetheless in the absence of their author continue

to accompany other forms of thought which, elaborated in new times . . .

propose to bring new developments to philosophical reection.

34

In fact, this ‘philosophical actuality’ of Spinoza’s thought in certain previous

Marxisms, and the belief that Spinoza is an important resource for the

contemporary regeneration of Marxism, has been the central argument of

recent Marxist Spinozist scholarship, most notably in the studies of Macherey,

Balibar, Negri and Montag.

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 83

reference for the NLR at the time of the composition of Considerations on Western
Marxism
) in his down-playing of this tradition (Montag 1998, p. x). The following
is Plekhanov’s account of his conversation with Engels in 1889 in London: ‘I had
the pleasure of spending almost a week in long discussions with him on various
practical and theoretical subjects. At one point our discussion turned to philosophy.
Engels strongly criticised what Stern rather imprecisely calls the “materialism in the
philosophy of nature”. “So for you”, I asked him, “old Spinoza was right when he
said that thought and extension were nothing but two attributes of one and the same
substance?” “Of course”, Engels replied, “old Spinoza was absolutely right” ’ (Colletti
1972, p. 72).

33

Montag 1998, p. ix.

34

Macherey 1998, p. 126.

background image

‘Marx’s only direct ancestor’

Similarly, publications after the composition of Considerations on Western

Marxism cast doubt upon the assimilation of Althusser ’s Spinozism to a
general trend in Western Marxism to supplement Marxism with themes drawn

from pre-Marxist philosophy. Certainly, the often dramatic, rarely textually

speciŽc (and sometimes contradictory) pronouncements ex cathedra regard-
ing Spinoza in For Marx and Reading Capital seem to suggest that Althusser
thought of Spinoza’s work as ‘a prior vantage-point from which to interpret

the meaning of Marx’s work itself’ in much the same way as had been done

by previous Western Marxist theorists in relation to Hegel.

35

For instance,

in Reading Capital, Althusser elaborated his notion of an ‘historical fact . . . as

a fact which causes a mutation in the existing structural relations’, as a prelude
to his deŽnition of ‘philosophical events of historical scope’ as those ‘which cause
real mutations in the existing philosophical structural relations, in this case
the existing theoretical problematic’.

36

As a paradigmatic example of such a

mutation, he then offered the case of Spinoza. He declared that

Spinoza’s philosophy introduced an unprecedented theoretical revolution

in the history of philosophy, probably the greatest philosophical revolution

of all time, insofar as we can regard Spinoza as Marx’s only direct ances-

tor, from the philosophical standpoint.

37

Similarly, in For Marx (in the essay ‘On the Young Marx’), Althusser proposed
that, rather than sublating Hegel, as much of both classical and Western

Marxism had supposed, Marx had instead ‘retreated’ or ‘returned’ to real his-

tory in order to found a scientiŽc discourse freed from ideological mystiŽcation.

Althusser drew the conclusion that science (Marxism) was not, therefore, the

‘truth’ of ideology (philosophy), but, rather, was an alternative thought-form

generated by returning to ‘the authentic objects which [were] (logically and

historically) prior to the ideology which has reected them and hemmed

them in’.

38

As a part of his clariŽcation of this thesis, he then proposed that

science can by no criteria be regarded as the truth of ideology in the Hegelian

sense. If we want a historical predecessor to Marx in this respect we

84 • Peter Thomas

35

Anderson 1976, p. 59.

36

Althusser and Balibar 1970, p. 102.

37

Ibid.

38

Althusser 1977, p. 77.

background image

must appeal to Spinoza rather than Hegel. Spinoza established a relation

between the Žrst and the second kind of knowledge which, in its immedi-

acy (abstracting from the totality in God), presupposed precisely a radical

discontinuity. Although the second kind makes possible the understanding

of the Žrst, it is not its truth.

39

Assertions like these, therefore, make Anderson’s conclusion – that behind

Althusser’s general (and rhetorical) assertions about Spinoza’s relation to

Marx was a developed and coherent argument which posited Spinoza, rather

than Hegel, as the philosophical ground from which to understand Marx –

understandable.

40

Yet, shortly after Considerations on Western Marxism was

written, and shortly before it was published, Althusser’s Éléments d’Autocritique
(1974) appeared, in one of whose chapters Althusser offered a more complex

account of his reference to Spinoza. This is not to say that he clariŽed the

speciŽc substantive points of agreement or divergence between his thought

and Spinoza’s. As Anderson remarked in a footnote attached to his analysis

after this event, Althusser’s ‘account [of his relation to Spinoza] remains vague

and generic, characteristically lacking textual references and speciŽc corre-

spondences’.

41

Nor is it to claim that Althusser retracted his claim for the

relevance of Spinoza to the understanding of the genesis of Marxism. Even

more than the brief comments in Reading Capital and For Marx, the chapter
on Spinoza in Essays in Self Criticism makes large claims regarding the afŽnities
of Marx and Spinoza, and attempts to offer further arguments (schematically,

and in an undeveloped form) for Spinoza’s solitary preŽguration of Marx’s

thought. What Althusser did offer in this text, however, and which must

surely temper any judgement that he was simply following in a long line

of Western Marxist turns to pre-Marxist philosophy in order to ‘legitimate,

explicate or supplement the philosophy of Marx himself’, was an extended

meditation on his encounter with Spinoza, in philosophical, personal and

political terms. From this text, it can be seen, in retrospect, that the most

signiŽcant feature of Althusser’s relation to Spinoza was less the substantive

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 85

39

Althusser 1977, p. 78.

40

Further declarations which seem to endorse Anderson’s interpretation can be

found in Althusser ’s discussion of the distinction between the object of knowledge
and the real object (Althusser and Balibar 1970, p. 40), and the notion of structural
causality (Althusser and Balibar 1970, p. 187).

41

Anderson 1976, p. 66.

background image

claims he advanced regarding the afŽnity of Spinoza and Marx, than the

distinctive nature of the method of philosophical reading and activity he

claimed had informed this encounter. Rather than an explicator of Capital

avant la lettre, what Althusser found in Spinoza was instead a foil to facilitate

his understanding of Marx’s work and his own work’s relationship to it.

‘A detour . . . but with regard to another detour’

The rubric under which Althusser placed his engagement with Spinoza

was that of a detour, a term he used with a precise philosophical sense and
consciousness of its Marxist heritage. ‘Having for years banged our heads

against a wall of enigmatic texts and wretched commentaries on them’, he

remarked about the unresolved difŽculty of Marx’s mature work, ‘we had to

decide to step back and make a detour’.

42

Two reasons were offered for this

decision. First, Hegel’s thought had itself been founded upon a detour: a

detour via Spinoza. Or, rather, Hegel had proposed certain interpretations

and solutions to problems posed by Spinoza, which had resulted in the

distinctive orientation of his own system, which in turn (suitably ‘inverted’

and ‘demystiŽed’) had made possible Marx’s critical and materialist dialectic

(‘borrowed from the “most speculative” chapters of the Great Logic of Absolute
Idealism’).

43

Returning to Spinoza, therefore, provided the opportunity to

examine those radical features of Spinoza’s thought (primarily, its anti-

teleology and anti-subjectivism) which had been submerged in the Hegelian

synthesis, only tentatively to reappear – so Althusser argued – in the work

of Marx. As Althusser stated at one point in his comments, ‘Spinoza allows

us to perceive Hegel’s mistake’.

44

Thus far, it would appear that Althusser’s detour via Spinoza was consonant

with the Western Marxist urge to seek out a prior philosophical vantage point

for the purpose of understanding Marx, though the perceived philosophical

lineage on which this was based is such that it cannot easily be rejected

as an eclecticism diluting the purity of historical materialism with foreign

additions (as, for instance, Timpanaro’s supplementation of Marx with Leopardi

86 • Peter Thomas

42

Althusser 1976, p. 133.

43

Althusser 1976, p. 134.

44

Althusser 1976, p. 137.

background image

could be considered, although Anderson curiously regarded this case as a

possible exception to the Western Marxist tendency he condemned).

45

However,

Althusser ’s second reason for this detour decisively departs from the

template, and furthermore, seems to me to be a much more signiŽcant and

revealing account of the utility he found in reading Spinoza. For Althusser,

a philosophic detour was something more than his own idiosyncratic

solution to the general problem encountered by all who had attempted to

comprehend Marx: the singularity and complexity of his thought. On the

contrary, detours, or steps back, were essential to the practice of philosophy.

A philosophy, Althusser argued, ‘only exists in so far as it “works out”

its difference from other philosophies, from those which, by similarity or

contrast, help it to sense, perceive and grasp itself, so that it can take up its

own positions’.

46

This description applied to no philosophy more than it

did to Marx’s, whose own experience in fact formed the inspiration and the

model for Althusser’s theory of a detour. ‘What else did Marx do’, Althusser

asked, ‘throughout his endless research, but go back to Hegel in order to

rid himself of Hegel and to Žnd his own way, what else but rediscover

Hegel in order to distinguish himself from Hegel and to deŽne himself?’

47

To

emphasise this point, he further noted that ‘Marx . . . was not content with

making a single detour, via Hegel; he also constantly and explicitly, in his

insistent use of certain categories, measured himself against Aristotle, ‘that

great thinker of the Forms’.

48

Althusser, therefore, proposed that, in order to understand this dynamic

which had animated Marx’s own philosophic practice – thereby entering into

the interior of his thought and becoming capable of developing it further

to meet the new challenges which had arisen in the twentieth century – it

was necessary to mimic (or more generously, reproduce) the philosophic

procedures and conditions by and under which it had been originally pro-

duced. As Althusser acknowledged, the adoption of this strategy of repetition

entailed taking certain risks. Marx’s own philosophic detours, particularly

via Hegel, had not occurred without a theoretical cost (the coquetting with

Hegelian phraseology which Althusser thought had misled subsequent

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 87

45

Anderson 1976, pp. 60 & 91.

46

Althusser 1976, p. 133.

47

Ibid.

48

Althusser 1976, pp. 133–4.

background image

Marxists; the continuing re-emergence of Hegelian (ideological) concepts even

in Marx’s mature work; the always provisional status of the epistemological

break Althusser would propose in his later revision of the early theory’s

messianism). But it would only be possible to determine this cost, to under-

stand the price Marx had had to pay for his detours along with that now

risked by the Althusserian school, ‘by ourselves working on these detours’.

‘In our subjective history, and in the existing ideological and theoretical

conjuncture, this detour became a necessity’.

49

Thus, the primary reason and

motivation for his and his co-workers’ ‘step back’:

We made a detour via Spinoza in order to improve our understanding of

Marx’s philosophy. To be precise: since Marx’s materialism forced us to think

out the meaning of the necessary detour via Hegel, we made the detour via

Spinoza in order to clarify our understanding of Marx’s detour via Hegel. A detour,

therefore; but with regard to another detour.

50

Ironically, given Althusser’s reputation as the arch anti-Hegelian of the 1960s

(a perception which has become less tenable in recent years, with the publi-

cation of his early writings and their deep engagement with and critique of

the work of Hegel, rather than – like so many others – its mere rejection),

Althusser’s account of his detour via Spinoza seems performatively to conŽrm

the most Hegelian of philosophic procedures: the phenomenological attempt

to grasp the inner form of previous philosophies, as an element in under-

standing the organic relationships which composed them, recapitulating in

thought and in a condensed form the complex cognitive development which

formed the prehistory and conditions of possibility of continuing philosophical

practice. Like Hegel, Althusser attempted to ground this phenomenology

in history – that is, in the actual philosophic forms which had occurred in

previous epochs – by crafting a dense historical narrative which traced the

laborious and impeded emergence of what he proposed were the distinctive

features of Marx’s thought, a veritable Calvary of Marxist science; but also

similarly to Hegel, the importance of this condensed Bildungsroman, viewed
phenomenologically, was that it enabled Althusser’s thought to repeat and

internalise the signiŽcant features of those previous forms, in such a way that

he would be able to realise their potentials in his own practice.

88 • Peter Thomas

49

Althusser 1976, p. 134.

50

Ibid.

background image

A further dimension of the strongly affective, personal and at the same

time directly political nature of Althusser’s reading of Spinoza is revealed by

remarks originally written for his autobiography, but only recently published

in English as a chapter in The New Spinoza. Althusser’s admiration for Spinoza
as a philosophical strategist is clear; in fact, it is perhaps not exaggerating

to say that above and beyond any particular substantive philosophic propo-

sition, what most attracted Althusser to Spinoza was the subtle polemical

strategy of the Ethics, a ‘revolutionary philosophical strategy’ which Althusser
curiously compared to Mao’s theory of guerrilla warfare.

51

He said:

What also fascinated me in Spinoza was his philosophical strategy. . . .

Spinoza began with God! He began with God, and deep down inside

(I believe it, after the entire tradition of his worst enemies) he was (as were

da Costa and so many other Portuguese Jews of his time) an atheist.

A supreme strategy: he began by taking over the chief stronghold of his

adversary, or rather he established himself there as if he were his own

adversary, therefore not suspected of being the sworn adversary, and re-

disposed the theoretical fortress in such a way as to turn it completely

around, as one turns around cannons against the fortress’s own occupant. . . .

Generally this is not the way that a philosopher proceeds: they always

oppose from a certain exterior the forces of their theses, which are destined

to take over the domain protected and defended by previous theses, which

already occupy the terrain.

52

Althusser further commented that his interpretation of the conjunctural

nature of Spinoza’s thought had a profound impact upon his conception of

the political tasks confronting his own philosophical practice. Spinoza had

given ‘one of the greatest lessons in heresy that the world had ever seen’, by

occupying orthodox theological positions so deeply that he had transformed

them into their opposite, and by outwitting the theologians on their own

ground of rigorous scriptural interpretation.

53

Might it not then be possible,

Althusser seemed to muse, to effect a similar transformation of the reigning

orthodoxy of Stalinism, based as it was upon the near-scriptural status ascribed

to certain of Marx’s and Engels’s texts, and possessing its own distinctive

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 89

51

Althusser 1997, p. 11.

52

Althusser 1997, pp. 10–11.

53

Althusser 1976, p. 132.

background image

hermeneutic of ‘diamat’?

54

Again, it was not primarily a matter of arguing

that Spinoza was ‘Marx without a beard’, but, rather, of attempting to draw

inspiration from Spinoza in order to confront a set of contemporary problems

which seemed, at least to Althusser, to have been preŽgured in a previous

era, namely, the theological disputes of the late seventeenth century. As

Althusser revealingly reected, ‘no doubt this [Spinoza’s] strategy comforted

me in my personal philosophical and political strategy: to take over the Party

from inside its own positions . . . but what pretensions!’

55

The political implications of these pretensions will shortly be examined.

For now, Althusser’s theory of a philosophic detour should alert us to the

possibility that something more dynamic had occurred in his engagement

with Spinoza than a mere transcription, as Anderson’s third assumption

suggested. As we have seen, Anderson argued that many of the main fea-

tures of the Althusserian synthesis were ‘directly drawn’, ‘taken straight’,

‘faithfully derived’ from Spinoza.

56

This was undoubtedly the most serious

element in Anderson’s characterisation of the nature of Althusser’s relation-

ship to Spinoza, both in terms of its implicit and unargued assertions and

the effects its dismissive brevity have had on subsequent Anglophone Marxist

scholarship.

57

Implicit in it were two questionable, unargued assertions: Žrst,

the assertion that Althusser’s Marxism was not in fact his Marxism at all,
but, instead, the recycling of the themes of pre-Marxist metaphysics, the direct

transposition of Spinoza’s thought into twentieth-century Western Marx-

ism. In other words, the Althusserian system’s origin lay in the thought of

Spinoza (and in Anderson’s unfortunate choice of metaphors, he came close

to accusing Althusser of a sometimes-acknowledged plagiarism). Following

on from this was the second implicit assertion that the political failings of

90 • Peter Thomas

54

Althusser suggests such an interpretation in his autobiography, when he links

the appeal to Marx to the refusal of orthodoxy. Althusser 1994, p. 222.

55

Althusser 1997, p. 11, see also Althusser 1994, p. 222.

56

Anderson 1976, p. 64.

57

This brevity was perhaps unavoidable in a work whose main concern was with

themes other than Althusser’s Spinozism. Nevertheless, given the seriousness of his
assertions – particularly that Althusser had directly transcribed elements of Spinoza’s
thought – the absence of a full analysis of the nature and signiŽcance of this rela-
tionship remains a glaring omission which Anderson has not rectiŽed in a separate
and more extended study – despite asserting that ‘further study would have little
difŽculty in documenting’ the real extent and unity of the transposition of Spinoza’s
thought in Althusser ’s theoretical work (Anderson 1976, p. 66).

background image

Althusser’s work could, therefore, be traced to its dependence upon Spinoza,

or that Spinoza was, in some suitably indeterminate sense (as in the best of

all slanders), ‘responsible’ for those same failings.

58

The Žrst assertion makes

it impossible to think the speciŽcity and conditions of possibility of the

Althusserian initiative, and to learn the political lessons which Althusser’s

detour via Spinoza holds for those concerned to restore the Marxist unity of

theory and practice; the second gave rise to a tendency to judge the relevance

and fertility of Spinoza for Marxism on the basis of the perceived failings or

successes of Althusser’s project. Given Althusserianism’s spectacular fall from

grace in the late 1970s, the equation, in most instances and except for those

previously noted, has been deleterious. Both resulted in Anderson endors-

ing, unintentionally and against the central thesis of Considerations on Western

Marxism,

59

a theory of an ahistorical transfer of a philosophical essence

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 91

58

This may or may not have been the perspective behind Anderson’s characteri-

sation of Althusser ’s use of Spinoza; whatever his doubts about the relevance of
Spinoza’s metaphysics and political theory to twentieth-century Marxism, he has
expressed elsewhere admiration for the personal character of Spinoza (Anderson 1980,
p. 125). Nevertheless, his choice of metaphors had the predictable unfortunate effects
on the reputation of Spinoza among Anglophone Marxists. If Althusser = Spinoza,
then one can argue that Spinoza must bear at least some of the responsibility for
Althusser ’s errors as in, for example, the following comment of Simon Clarke. ‘In
this conception [the theory of Darstellung outlined in Reading Capital] the economic is
permanently present in the political and ideological realms, on the analogy of the
presence of the Freudian unconscious in the conscious as the “absent presence of a
present absence”. The economic, like Lacan’s unconscious, exists only in its effects. The
philosophical inspiration for this conception is not Marx but Spinoza
. It is only by recourse
to the Spinozist conception of the relation between God and Substance, with the eco-
nomic taking the role of God and the political the role of Substance
, that Althusser can Žnd
a place for the economic at all. Since it is only an act of faith that can establish the
determination, even in the last instance, of the economic once a secular, bourgeois,
conception of society is adopted, it is hardly surprising that Althusser ’s dominant
philosophical inspiration is that of metaphysical theology’ (Clarke 1980, pp. 84–5,
italics mine).

59

For the central thesis of Considerations on Western Marxism was that Western

Marxism’s philosophic detour was an effect of a complex political situation whose
cause was Stalinism and its reverberations throughout the international communist
and working-class movement. Anderson developed this analysis in great detail
and across an impressive range of theorists throughout this study. Yet, in his speciŽc
analysis of Althusser ’s relation to Spinoza, he characterised that relationship in terms
which seemed to attribute the failings of the Althusserian system to the derisory effects
of reading Spinoza – not to the complicated (and compromised) nature of Althusser’s
manoeuvring within the heavily Stalinised PCF (a fact even more noticeable given
that Anderson elsewhere has offered one of the more balanced political assessments
of Althusser ’s relationship to Stalinism (Anderson 1980, pp. 100–30)). In the absence
of these necessary historical considerations, Anderson’s depiction of the nature of

background image

from one thinker to another which has little in common with the tradition

inaugurated by The German Ideology. A properly Marxist intervention into
the Želd of the history of ideas cannot be content to posit an essential (or

even virtual) identity between different thinkers on the basis of an apparent

homology between their concepts. Rather, if there is a remarkable similarity

between Althusser’s and Spinoza’s concepts, it behoves an historical-mate-

rialist study to explain the complex interaction of intellectual, historical, and
political causes which produced such an extraordinary event.

The return of the repressed

Warren Montag’s work is the necessary starting point for developing such

an explanation. In a guarded critique of Anderson’s suggestion that Althusser

simply and directly transcribed central elements of Spinoza’s thought, Montag

has sought to demonstrate that, instead, a more determined relationship

obtained, one founded not merely in a subjective contingency on Althusser’s

part, but, much more importantly, in the similarity – and singularity – of the

historical circumstances in which these two philosophies were produced.

Montag argues that

To speak of the inuence of Spinoza on Althusser is already to grant a

conceptual régime that both thinkers refused. The term ‘inuence’ does not

begin to capture the way in which an important part of Althusser ’s work

is itself Spinozist, constituting a theoretical project profoundly internal to

the conceptual space delimited by Spinoza’s works. Of course, as Althusser

himself has said, this taking of positions was never simply the result of

a personal choice. It was rather that something of Spinoza’s theoretical

struggle, modiŽed by the relationship of theoretical forces that characterised

the latter half of the seventeenth century, repeated itself in the theoretical

conjuncture of 1960s France. This repetition, or return of the repressed,

signalled and continues to signal the existence of a conict to be analysed.

60

As Montag further argues, this repetition should not be understood in terms

of a simple reiteration of concepts. Rather, it was a repetition of conjunctural

92 • Peter Thomas

Althusser’s relationship to Spinoza committed the classic error which Spinoza denounced
as the source of all errors: mistaking effects for causes.

60

Montag 1993, pp. 51–2.

background image

features, or more exactly, the re-emergence of a distinctive philosophical and

political terrain, which allowed Althusser to attempt to ‘re-actualise’ signiŽcant

elements of Spinoza’s thought. When this situation is acknowledged, Montag

argues, the Spinozistic themes in Reading Capital which were incomprehen-
sible to many critics become explicable as

not an interpretation of Spinoza but an intervention in the relationship

of forces that governs his text, taking the side of certain hypotheses against

others, pushing these hypotheses to extreme conclusions, towards the

dismantling of a theoretical apparatus in which the notions of transcen-

dence, immateriality or ideality are dominant. This intervention produces

a materialism so thoroughgoing that it remains for Althusser ’s critics, as for

Spinoza’s three hundred years earlier, illegible and unthinkable.

61

In more recent work, Montag has attempted to specify those features of

Spinoza’s thought which made it amenable to such a ‘re-actualisation’ or

‘re-deployment’. ‘Spinoza’s works’, Montag argues,

constitute a philosophy that never deŽnitively closes upon itself, that is

never strictly identiŽable with a Žnite set of propositions or arguments that

would allow it to be categorised once and for all as ‘rationalist’ or even

‘materialist’.

62

He emphasises that this ‘openness’ should not be understood as an indeter-

minacy or ambiguity of Spinoza’s thought, but, rather, as a function of the

central philosophical strategy of the Ethics – the operation of the Sive (in André
Tosel’s phrase), which was the foundation of Spinoza’s famous depiction of

the one substance as Deus sive Natura. ‘This philosophical slogan’, Montag
argues, ‘summarizes both the content and the form of Spinoza’s philosophy

in the very fact that it simultaneously afŽrms and denies that it afŽrms

the radical abolition of transcendence’. ‘The Žrst term is translated into and

then displaced by the second. God disappears into nature’

63

– but such a

translation and displacement must necessarily always remain provisional.

Having abandoned all a priori transcendental guarantees, Spinoza’s denial
of transcendence can only become ‘actual’, Montag suggests, when it is

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 93

61

Montag 1993, p. 52.

62

Montag and Stolze (eds.) 1997, p. x.

63

Montag 1999, p. 4.

background image

linked to the movements of the multitude which themselves seek to reassert

their immanent power (potentia) against the Power (potestas) of transcendent
authority. The 1960s witnessed such a moment, thus making possible the

re-emergence of Spinozistic themes in the Althusserian initiative. When those

conditions were eclipsed by the reaction of the 1980s and 1990s, materialist

philosophies of immanence such as Althusser’s and Spinoza’s necessarily

began to once more appear ‘illegible and unthinkable’.

This interpretation represents a real advance over that proposed in Con-

siderations on Western Marxism. By refusing a rhetoric of ‘origins’ or ‘inuence’
and, instead, seeking to comprehend the ‘actuality’ of Spinoza’s thought

in Althusser, Montag is able to move to a consideration of the substantive

problems with which both thinkers attempted to deal, rather than a formal-

ist dismissal of them. In particular, his treatment of Althusser’s Spinozism

is the site of the development of a sophisticated materialist theory of the

relations between thought-forms from different eras. In Benjaminian terms,

Montag’s analysis can be said to characterise Althusser’s Spinozism as a

seizing ‘hold of a memory’ when it ashed up at ‘a moment of danger’, the

forging of an alliance across the centuries with another thinker who had

attempted to remain a ‘heretic in the truth’, through which Althusser sought

to gain theoretical resources for his attempt to provide an immanent critique

of the reigning Stalinist orthodoxy in the PCF and the international Communist

movement.

64

By emphasising that this alliance was no mere repetition, but a

development of a long-neglected materialist anti-transcendentalism, Montag

makes it possible to think the positive and politically enabling features of

Althusser’s Spinozism.

Nevertheless, it seems to me that, in at least one respect, Montag’s analysis

remains incomplete: namely, it does not open up the space to think that which

divides Althusser from Spinoza as much as that which unites them. Attempting

94 • Peter Thomas

64

Benjamin 1970, p. 257. Althusser ’s Augustinian commitment to the PCF (and

his coquetting with Maoism) necessarily complicated and perhaps compromised
the genesis and effects of his critique. To note this political origin is to remember
Althusser ’s work as a concrete intervention into a concrete political conjuncture. This
is particularly important given, on the one hand, the still lingering Thompsonian
prejudice, perhaps more often thought in the general Marxist culture than stated in
scholarly studies, that Althusserianism was little more than Stalinism theorised as
ideology; and, on the other, the tendency to treat Althusser ’s categories as neutral
ahistorical techniques to be absorbed into the arsenal of bourgeois social science.

background image

to think the differences between Althusser and Spinoza (sometimes, as we

shall see, within their apparent identity) is equally as important to the reassess-

ment of the Althusserian legacy as is defending his detour via Spinoza from

rash charges of heresy. This is because such a consideration allows us to think

both the positive and negative consequences of this detour, and, therefore,

the lessons it holds for contemporary attempts to reinvigorate historical mate-

rialism by means of similar methods. In order to open up this space, and as

a Žrst attempt to theorise one element of Althusser’s detour, I will therefore

propose the following thesis: rather than the direct transcription of Spinoza’s

thought asserted by Anderson, or the continuation and development pro-

posed by Montag, Althusser’s Spinozism can be characterised as involving

a very complicated transposition of the formal structures of Spinoza’s thought
onto the very different content of twentieth-century Marxist politics.

65

If this

transposition allowed Althusser to make an important contribution to the

ongoing development of Marxist theory, it was not achieved, as Althusser

knew only too well, without taking certain risks, the price of which was

potentially negative political and theoretical consequences. In order to demon-

strate the feasibility of this thesis I will conclude by comparing two of

the central propositions of Spinoza’s and Althusser’s thought: Spinoza’s

equation of cause and effect implicit in his notion of God as an immanent

cause, and the Althusserian notion of ‘structural causality’. If, at Žrst glance,

Althusser’s notion appears to have sprung fully grown from the head of

Spinoza, this apparent similarity conceals deeper, historical and substantive,

discrepancies between the two thinkers which can only be comprehended

through developing a fully historicised account of the nature of their rela-

tionship and their concepts.

66

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 95

65

Obviously, I am not suggesting that Althusser adopted the infamously difŽcult

mode of presentation of the Ethics (more geometrico). Rather, I am referring to Althusser’s
redeployment of elements of Spinoza’s philosophical strategy, primarily, the treatment
of the relations between concepts, between concepts and objects, and the ways of
transforming both of these. Clearly, this strictly philosophical thesis will require
modiŽcation when it is brought into relation with an explicit consideration of the
other elements of Althusser ’s detour (the historical and the political), which I hope
to attempt in a future study.

66

Space will not permit an analysis of the other, formally similar, notions of

Althusser and Spinoza which were nominated by Anderson. At least one pair of these,
however, should be noted as a fertile Želd for further research: Spinoza’s theory of
the imagination and Althusser’s theory/theories of ideology. (Spinoza’s theory of the

background image

Deus sive Natura

Spinoza scandalised the theological establishment of the seventeenth cen-

tury by asserting that God was ‘the immanent, not the transitive, cause of

all things’.

67

In the place of the transcendent creator of Judeo-Christian

orthodoxy, a God (the inŽnite) conceived of as prior to and external to his

creations (the Žnite), Spinoza posited that there was only one substance (Deus

sive Natura), a being absolutely inŽnite and self-caused (causa sui), consisting

of an inŽnity of attributes

68

– by which the intellect was able to perceive

the essence of substance – and modiŽed into the different modes which

comprised the entities of the Žnite world. It made no sense to talk of an

omniscient, omnipotent, inŽnite God, as both Jewish and Christian ortho-

doxy did, if God was then depicted as possessing attributes similar to those of

a human: a will, desire, and appetite, all signs of imperfection and limitation.

The only solution to this contradiction, Spinoza argued, was to conceive of

God as a true instead of false inŽnite, as an absolutely inŽnite being of inŽnite

powers, on whom no limitation could be placed. Counterposing the inŽnite,

conceived as an abstraction, to the concreteness of the Žnite, was the Žrst

(human, all too human) prejudice which needed to be overcome. As Althusser

recognised, Spinoza had overturned the theological certainties of his time by

pressing their own logic to a conclusion, until they were transformed into

96 • Peter Thomas

imagination was in fact the subject of some of Althusser’s most speciŽc and detailed
observations vis-à-vis his relation to Spinoza, particularly in the essay published in
The New Spinoza). A close examination of the relations of similarity and divergence
between these theories, and the historical causes for these relations, might help to
counter the still widespread prejudice that the Althusserian notion is nothing more
than poorly disguised Stalinism. Furthermore, attending to the development of the
relationship between imagination and superstition in Spinoza’s political texts might
help to clarify some of the ambiguities which I believe Althusser introduced into his
original treatment of the notion of ideology in ‘Marxism and Humanism’ by his later
revisions in the celebrated ‘Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses’.

67

EIP18.

68

It is important to note that Spinoza does not, as is often supposed, posit only

two attributes (thought and extension) of the one substance. As a ‘being absolutely
inŽnite’, God necessarily consists of ‘an inŽnity of attributes, of which each one
expresses an eternal and inŽnite essence’ (EID6). Only two, thought and extension,
are treated in the Ethics, because it is, precisely, an ethics rather than a metaphysics
or encyclopaedic system. As Spinoza states in the Preface to Book II, ‘I pass now to
explaining those things which must necessarily follow from the essence of God, or
the inŽnite and eternal being – not, indeed, all of them . . . but only those that
can lead us, by the hand, as it were, to the knowledge of the human mind and its
highest blessedness.’

background image

something quite other than what the orthodoxy intended. Spinoza did not

regard himself as an atheist – his response to his critics was, in effect, the

famous maxim of Epicurus: ‘Impiety does not consist in destroying the gods

of the crowd but rather in ascribing to the gods the ideas of the crowd’. But

the consequences of what Althusser called Spinoza’s ‘unparalleled audacity’

was to prepare the way for a fully secularised conception of the universe,

a plane of immanence, in Deleuze’s phrase, which could be explained on

its own terms and without reference to a beyond which determined and

guided it.

69

It was this argument, more than any other, which led to the reputation

of Spinozism during most of the eighteenth century as a most perŽdious

atheism. In the changed conjuncture of German romanticism and its after-

math, however, a different interpretation of Spinoza’s Deus sive Natura began
to gain ascendancy – for Novalis, Spinoza was the God-intoxicated man; for

Hegel, the problem with Spinoza was that far from his denying the divine,

‘with him there is too much God’.

70

Yet Spinoza’s contemporaries recognised

his philosophy for what it was in its own conjuncture: an intervention against

the pretensions of the orthodox theology of the time to maintain the inŽnite

as a beyond from which the Žnite world was derivative and to which it was

secondary. If the concept of God encompassed everything, then the term lost

all critical force to distinguish between states of corruption and perfection,

the Žnite and the inŽnite, this world and a beyond – distinctions which were

absolutely crucial not only for defending the religious orthodoxy of the day

but also for maintaining the political status quo. As both Balibar and Negri

have recently stressed, this theological critique cannot be separated from its

political context: in the seventeenth century, theological disputes were directly

political. Deprived of a distinct status, Deus sive Natura soon became merely
Natura, a reduction which did not bode well for that other increasingly

dominant duality of the period, Monarch sive State. Spinoza’s critique of
traditional Judeo-Christian conceptions of God in the Ethics was in fact tied,

in the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, to a critique of the foundations of theo-
cratic political institutions in the history of the Jewish people, and, in the

Tractatus Politicus, he extended and reworked this perspective into a critique

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 97

69

Althusser 1997, p. 11.

70

Hegel 1995, p. 282.

background image

of all political formations which transferred the democratic power of the

multitude to a particular individual or class.

A further, crucial consequence of this proposition was that it led Spinoza

to reject abstract, mystiŽcatory explanations of phenomena, in favour of

concrete knowledge of their determinants. If ‘Nature herself is the power

of God under another name, and our ignorance of the power of God is co-

extensive with our ignorance of Nature’, it followed that it was ‘absolute

folly, therefore, to ascribe an event to the power of God when we know

not its natural cause, which is the power of God’.

71

Phenomena were to be

explained according to the order of causation which obtained in one of the

inŽnite attributes, not through reference to an inexplicable and inscrutable

divinity who stood outside the order of nature. Spinoza put this thesis to

devastating use with regard to the nature and origin of prophecy and mira-

cles in the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, and, at the same time, inaugurated

a materialist tradition of reading (continued in our own time by Althusser

and Derrida) which refuses a hermeneutics which would posit a text’s con-

ditions of intelligibility as exterior to its own material, discursive existence.

‘Knowledge . . . of the contents of Scripture,’ Spinoza argued, ‘must be sought

from Scripture alone, even as the knowledge of nature is sought from nature’,

rather than through deference to a supplementary interpretative tradition.

72

The foundation of this attempt was to examine Scripture ‘in the light of its

history’, that is, to produce a rational account of the conditions of produc-

tion, dissemination and (often) corruption of a text whose historicity had

been made incomprehensible by its subsequent elevation to a divinely inspired

status – in much the same way that rational knowledge of nature and humans

within it had been obscured by the notion that the ultimate cause of their

being was separate from them.

73

In short, Spinoza’s proposition that Deus

sive Natura was self-caused (causa sui) and inŽnite demanded a rejection of

98 • Peter Thomas

71

Spinoza 1951, p. 25.

72

Spinoza 1951, p. 100.

73

Spinoza 1951, p. 101. As André Tosel notes, ‘Spinoza thus establishes a parallel

between the Bible and Nature, but this analogy does not lend itself to operations
of a spiritualist kind. It is not Nature that becomes a text or a book; it is instead
texts and the Bible that become Nature, that is, natural objects open to a natural
interpretation. It is no longer a question of an analogy but of an explanation’ (Tosel
1997, p. 159).

background image

all forms of falsifying abstraction, and a search by the intellect for concrete,

comprehensible and explicable reasons, considered sub specie aeternitatis.

‘A cause immanent in its effects . . . in the Spinozist sense
of the term’

Althusser’s notion of structural causality is, indeed, formally similar to this

Spinozist critique of a transcendental notion of causality. The general co-

ordinates of this notion are well known. While Spinoza’s immediate point of

reference was theology, Althusser’s was the two theories of causation of the

social totality which he argued had dominated previous Marxism. In Reading

Capital, he claimed that

classical philosophy . . . had two and only two systems of concepts with

which to think effectivity. The mechanistic system, Cartesian in origin, which

reduced causality to a transitive and analytical effectivity [and] the Leibnizian

concept of expression.

74

Those traditions within Marxism which he branded as ‘economist’ had, accord-

ing to Althusser, conceived of the determination of the superstructure by the

base/infrastructure in transitive terms. The crushing of the Left Opposition,

the rise of Stalin’s socialism in one country, and the institution of state-directed

production plans had been accompanied by the elevation of a strict notion

of economic determinism (based upon a distorted reading of the base and

superstructure metaphor) to a centrality and orthodox status it did not

possess during the period of classical historical materialism.

75

Although

Althusser would not have accepted this foregoing narrative at any stage in

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 99

74

Althusser and Balibar 1970, p. 186.

75

Space does not permit the full argument required by this assertion. Nor will I

attempt to arbitrate between those views which see Stalinist economism as a defor-
mation of a more sophisticated pre-Stalinist Marxism (as I do), and those, like the late
Althusser’s, which view it as the ‘posthumous revenge of the Second International’
(Althusser 1976, p. 89). I will simply note that, despite the bacchanalian fantasies of
the anti- and post-Marxist imaginary, a close reading of the texts of Marx, Engels,
Lenin, Luxemburg, Trotsky, Lukács and Gramsci (among others) reveals vulgar
economic determinism as less a fundamental tenet of Marxism, than a corruption
used to justify the forced labour camp called the USSR and the cretinisation of the
international communist movement in the interests of Soviet imperialism – a verita-
ble Deus ex Machina called upon to cover up state capitalism’s economic, political and
moral bankruptcy.

background image

his philosophical and political evolution, it nevertheless seems to me that his

rejection of ‘economism’ is properly understood as a rejection of one of the

central ideological tenets of Stalinism, in favour of a model of causality which

acknowledged the much more complex process of determination between

the various practices which constituted the social whole. In economism, he

argued, the economy was posited as a Žrst cause which preceded and remained

separate from its effects in the determined superstructure, which were

then seen as derivative and epiphenomenal. He rejected this notion of social

causation as not only mechanistic and transitive, but also as a transcenden-

tal notion which, despite its seemingly secular orientation, was secretly

modelled on the properly theological conception of a God who exercised his

creative powers to bring the Žnite world into being.

On the other hand, just as economism relied upon mechanical – i.e. undi-

alectical, pre-Marxist – notions, Althusser argued that the alternative notion

of ‘expressivism’ had also resulted in a relapse to a pre-Marxist theory of

causation – in this instance, a Leibnizian-Hegelian model which posited the

determination of the particular by the universal, or an essence of the whole

which was expressed in each particular phenomenal form. Some critics

have seen in this particular critique a coded attack upon Stalinism similar

to that implicit in Althusser’s rejection of ‘economism’.

76

Many more have

argued that the tendency Althusser had in his sights in this case was, in fact,

that of previous Western Marxism’s focus upon the notion of totality as an

alternative to Stalinist orthodoxy. Althusser’s characterisation of previous

Western Marxism’s notion of totality and dismissal of the interpretation of

the theory of commodity fetishism which derived from it (particularly as

it was developed in the founding text of that tradition, ‘ReiŽcation and

the Class Consciousness of the Proletariat’, the central essay of Lukács’s

History and Class Consciousness) is far from uncontentious. However, whether

correctly or not, Althusser argued that this expressivist model, although

distinct from (transitive) economism, in that it refused the notion of a privi-

leged Žrst cause outside the order of causation, was nevertheless complicit

with economism, insofar as it continued to posit a cause which remained

strictly separate from its effects, even as it entered into a dynamic relation-

ship with them.

77

He argued that

100 • Peter Thomas

76

See, in particular, Jameson 1981, pp. 37–8.

77

The difference between transitive-economist and spiritual-expressivist accounts

background image

The Hegelian totality is the alienated development of a simple unity, of

a simple principle, itself a moment of the development of the Idea: so,

strictly speaking, it is the phenomenon, the self-manifestation of this

simple principle which persists in all its manifestations, and therefore

even in the alienation which prepares its restoration.

78

Althusser’s theory of Marx’s epistemological break with Hegel required

him to reject such a model of causation as non-Marxist. His alternative,

following certain brief passages in Marx,

79

was the notion of structural

causality, in which

the structure is immanent in its effects, a cause immanent in its effects

in the Spinozist sense of the term, . . . the whole existence of the structure

consists of its effects, in short . . . the structure, which is merely a speciŽc

combination of its peculiar elements, is nothing outside its effects.

80

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 101

of causation could be characterised in theological terms as the difference between
an Hebraic creatio ex nihilo and a neo-Platonic emanation – the two great rivals of
the early Christian church, which Althusser condemned as inadequate for the
comprehension of the distinctly secular object of modern society. At the same time,
however, I believe it remains to be determined by future research whether or not the
theory of structural causality does not itself run the risk of collapsing back into an
emanationist model, and thus whether Andrew Collier is correct to argue that ‘the
Spinozian conception of structural causality applied to society’ is indeed the only
foundation of ‘scientiŽc politics’ (Collier 1989, p. 83).

78

Althusser and Balibar 1970, p. 203. See also the following: ‘The Hegelia n

totality may be said to be endowed with a unity of a “spiritual” type in which each
element is pars totalis, and in which the visible spheres are merely the alienated and
restored unfolding of the said internal principle’ (Althusser and Balibar 1970, p. 204).

79

The most signiŽcant was the following suggestive description from the Grundrisse:

‘In all forms of society it is a determinate production and its relations which assign
every other production and its relations their rank and inuence. It is a general
illumination [Beleuchtung] in which all the other colours are plunged and which
modiŽes their special tonalities. It is a special ether which deŽnes the speciŽc weight
of every existence arising in it’ (Marx 1973, pp. 106–7; quoted in Althusser and Balibar
1970, p. 187). It is important to note, as Althusser did, but as some of his followers
have not, that, in this instance, Marx was referring to the dominance in different
historic periods of speciŽc forms of economic production i.e. agriculture, industry etc.

80

Althusser and Balibar 1970, p. 189. Another example of the anti-transcendental

dimensions which had informed Althusser ’s thought can be found in the following:

The structure is not an essence outside the economic phenomena which
comes and alters their aspect, forms and relations and which is effective on
them as an absent cause, absent because it is outside them. The absence of the
cause in the structure’s ‘metonymic causality’ on its effects is not the fault of
the exteriority of the structure with respect to the economic phenomena; on the
contrary, it is the very form of the interiority of the structure, as a structure, in its

background image

This notion was similar to an expressivist (Hegelian) account of the totality,

in that it focused upon the relationship of elements within the whole (rather

than the originary moment of economism), but distinct from it, due to its

rejection of a uniŽed and unifying centre, maintaining its integrity through-

out its particular embodiments, and thus producing a symmetrical totality

in which the various elements were equivalent to one another as phenomena

proceeding from the totality’s essence. In place of such an essence, the notion

of structural causality posited the dynamic determination of all elements by

each other in a decentred ‘structure of structures’ (overdetermination), an

asymmetrical totality in which one element was dominant in any particular

conjuncture. This dominant element was determined by the economy, but,

unlike a strictly economist model, the economy was not necessarily itself the
dominant element.

81

Wary of any collapse back into economism, Althusser

had further added, to the continuing perplexity of both his critics and pro-

ponents alike, that ‘the lonely hour of the last instance never comes’.

82

In

102 • Peter Thomas

effects. This implies therefore that the effects are not outside the structure, are
not a pre-existing object, element or space in which the structure arrives to
imprint its mark. (Althusser and Balibar 1970, pp. 188–9).

Also relevant in this regard is the notion of an ‘authorless theatre’ developed in
Althusser and Balibar 1970, p. 193.

81

Althusser and Balibar 1970, p. 319.

82

Althusser 1977, p. 113. The difŽculty of this seemingly contradictory qualiŽcation

can, perhaps, be lessened by noting both its conjunctural and substantive import. In
terms of the former, it is important to recognise that the notion that ‘the lonely hour
of the last instance never comes’ was an essentially polemical formulation. Having
rejected economism, but nevertheless refusing the symmetry of an expressivist model,
Althusser ’s notion assigned the economic the role of ‘determining dominance’; and
then, in a second move, in order to prevent the surreptitious restoration of econom-
ism, he had immediately stressed the complexity of this process of ‘determining
dominance’, as against the simple, transitive role played by the economy in an
economist model. See the following formulation: ‘the economic dialectic is never active
in the pure state; in History, these instances, the superstructures, etc. – are never seen
to step respectfully aside when their work is done or, when the time comes, as his
pure phenomena, to scatter before His Majesty the Economy as he strides along the
royal road of the Dialectic. From the Žrst moment to the last, the lonely hour of
the last instance never comes’ (Althusser 1977, p. 113). In substantive terms, if the
priority accorded to the economic in the notion of structural causality was less than
that posited by economism, it was still required to be more than in an expressivist
model of causation. It was less than economism, because the economy determined
not the social totality itself but its dominant element at any particular moment. Yet it
was also more than expressivism, because Althusser ’s repudiation of an essence or
centre which manifested itself in its various phenomena (and whose self-alienation
and self-restoration had been the driving force of the Hegelian totality) required him
to locate the totality’s displaced dynamism in one of its elements, namely, the

background image

Spinozist terms, the economic Žgured as one of the elements or ‘attributes’

(alongside ideology, politics, culture etc.) gathered together underneath

the umbrella of the ‘one substance’ of the mode of production (but in asym-

metrical relation to those other elements, unlike the symmetry of Spinoza’s

attributes). Or, in phrases more Althusserian: rather than viewing society as

being determined by a single element (the economy), or as a self-alienating

and self-restoring totality which subsumed its parts within its (spiritual) unity,

the Althusserian notion of structural causality posited that society was a

decentred structure in dominance, subject to the contradictions, uneven

development and overdetermination of each of the relatively autonomous

elements within it, and it was this process itself – the structural interaction

of each of the elements upon each other and upon the whole – which was

the cause of the social totality. The social totality was an effect of a cause,

which was none other than the totality’s own self-production, or, as Althusser

sometimes phrased it, an ‘absent cause’, discernible only in its effects.

83

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 103

economic. The unresolved ambiguity of this central feature of Althusser ’s theory
played a not insigniŽcant role in the unravelling of the Althusserian paradigm, often
in the direction of abandoning the claim of the economy’s role in determining
the dominant element of any particular formation, and which then often led to
the elimination of the adjective in the phrase ‘relative autonomy’ to produce the
‘pluralism’ Althusser explicitly repudiated. See Althusser 1977, pp. 201–2.

83

Although this phrase was sometimes used by Althusser in relation to the theory

of structural causality, it seems to me to have remained a rhetorical ourish rather
than a developed category (for Althusser ’s own comments on the curious conditions
surrounding the production of this concept in the Capital reading group of 1964–5
at the École normale supérieure, see Althusser 1994, pp. 208–9, 352–3). Despite some
suggestive remarks in Essays in Self-Criticism and related writings, Althusser failed
to clarify the precise nature of the relationship between his notion of an ‘absent
cause’ and Spinoza’s causa immanens. Many of Althusser ’s Anglophone commenta-
tors, however, present ‘Spinoza’s idea of the “absent cause”’ (Jameson 1981, p. 35: cf.
Jay 1984, p. 409) as a verity. It is important to note two points. First, for Spinoza, ‘God
is the immanent, not the transitive, cause of all things’ (EIP18). He is not an absent
cause, but a cause pervasively present throughout its effects. To speak of an absent
cause in Spinoza is either to neglect the fact that particular entities are modiŽcations
within the one substance (and therefore that the cause of their being is not separate
from them, as the term ‘absent’ implies), or implicitly to restore a transitive notion of
causation, in which a once-present entity is subsequently absent (God as a catalyst
who disappears into his creations once the order of causation is set in motion, rather
than a prime mover eternally separate). But, for Spinoza, the identity of cause and
effect is immediate, eternal and inŽnite. Second, as Althusser used this phrase, and
as his commentators appear to have understood it, it seems to me to involve a conation
of the notion of structural causality (present throughout the social totality, a cause
only discernible in its effects [eine Beleuchtung]) with the related but distinct Althusserian
notion of a ‘symptomatic reading’. Symptomatic reading’s emphasis on explaining

background image

In short, just as Spinoza had done, Althusser arraigned his opponents with

unjustiŽably positing the cause of social phenomena (either the economy or

the essence of the social totality) as existing apart from its effects. The notion

of structural causality expressed a vision of society as a decentred structure

of structures, subject to the overdetermination and uneven development of

each of the structures within it, in which (paraphrasing Derrida) ‘there was

nothing outside of the social totality’ – that is, no privileged agent or essence

which was either prior to, distinct from, or exterior to the society which

they produced. Similarly, just as Spinoza’s refusal to locate the cause of Žnite

entities in an other-worldly beyond enabled him to attempt rationally to

understand the interrelationship of parts within the whole, without reference

to an unknown and unknowable ultimate guarantee, the notion of structural

causality sought to provide explanations for the phenomena of social life

according to thoroughly immanent criteria. It was an attempt to grasp the

self-productive complexity of society as a totality, without reference to either

a prime mover or spiritual essence which stood unaffected outside of that

production process.

Partial and limited totalities

Yet, despite these similarities, there remain important differences between

Althusser’s and Spinoza’s critiques. First, and most obviously, they sought

to explain different objects. Spinoza’s Deus sive Natura, or one substance,

encompassed everything under the sun (and some more), as they were always

and everywhere, viewed sub specie aeternitatis. The one substance was ‘deter-

mined to act by itself alone’,

84

or, as Spinoza argued in Proposition 17 of Book

I of the Ethics, ‘God acts from the laws of his nature alone, and is compelled

by no one’.

85

A social totality, on the other hand, is an ensemble of human

practices, and, as such, is an historically speciŽc formation. Furthermore, it

104 • Peter Thomas

(rather than resolving or effacing) a text’s contradictions, and on the determinant
absence (and therefore presence) of certain themes in a thinker ’s problematic is a
genuine case of an ‘absent cause’, of a cause absent from its effects, i.e. the text’s
material form. Structural causality’s ‘absent cause’, on the other hand, only makes
sense insofar as it is understood as continuing Althusser ’s polemic against transitive
models of social causation. Taken on its own, it contradicts his claim for the presence
of the social totality’s cause in the dynamic of its elements’ interrelationships.

84

EIDvii.

85

EIP17.

background image

is subject to external determinations, both from previous societies whose

formations continue to exert practical force (‘the weight of all the dead

generations’), and by the limits placed upon human practices by their inter-

action with and interpenetration by other natural, non-human, forces. Spinoza

rejected the notion that human society was a ‘dominion within a dominion’,

in which ‘man disturbs, rather than follows, the order of Nature’, ‘determined

only by himself’,

86

because he was polemicising against the view that man

was an autonomous subject endowed with a will which suspended the

laws of nature. Yet there is another, equally Spinozist, sense in which a social

totality must be thought of as a ‘totality within a totality’. A social totality,

or human society, is a limited subset of the genuinely inŽnite and eternal

totality of Natura, i.e. it is a Žnite modiŽcation within the one substance, and
as such, must be viewed sub specie durationis. As a Žnite modiŽcation, it is
not sufŽcient unto itself; it ‘is in another through which it is also conceived’,

87

and, unlike Spinoza’s self-caused one substance, its existence is not identical

with its essence

88

nor is it necessary,

89

but historically conditioned and con-

tingent. Stated simply, a social totality is a partial totality, which derives

its being from, and whose comprehension therefore requires reference

to, another, more inclusive totality. These totalities are not merely different

in terms of appearance; they are objects of a qualitatively different type. One

is a genuinely inŽnite totality, in its essence unbounded by any particular

determination; the other is, by deŽnition, restricted to human practices as

they are constituted in social formations. In a strict sense, they are incom-

mensurable. Properties discerned in one cannot automatically be attributed

to the other, nor can they be explained by reference to the same criteria.

This qualitative difference of the totalities – which Althusser and Spinoza

sought to comprehend – produced a second divergence in their thought: the

different consequences of their critiques. I have already noted Althusser’s

declared admiration for Spinoza’s philosophical strategy, and his attempt to

draw inspiration from Spinoza’s polemic with the theologians for his own

intervention in debates over the cause of the social totality. ‘I was fascinated

by this unparalleled audacity’, Althusser wrote of Spinoza’s transformation

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 105

86

EIIIPref.

87

EIDv.

88

EIDi.

89

EIP11.

background image

of his opponents’ theses by pressing their own logic to an extreme.

90

Just as

Spinoza had dissolved cause into effect, the notion of structural causality

attempted to abandon a transcendental notion of the social totality’s cause

in favour of an account in which there was nothing outside of the social

totality. Yet, because of the historical distance separating their critiques, and

because these totalities are incommensurable, Althusser’s employment of

formally similar philosophical procedures did not yield the same results.

Arguably, in analysing a social totality as if it were of the same type as

Spinoza’s one substance (in effect, conating these two distinct totalities

and the methods of analysis proper to each), the Althusserian notion of

structural causality ran the risk of producing effects which, in the speciŽc

conditions of the late twentieth century, were very different from those

which Spinoza’s critique had produced in its own particular conjuncture. I

am referring here to the ‘confused knowledges’ which Žgured prominently

in the decomposition of the original Althusserian moment, and which formed

the basis for many of the hostile critiques of Althusser’s own work, such as

Hindess and Hirst or E.P. Thompson. These can not simply be attributed to

external determinations, or, in Spinoza’s terms, ‘unfortuitious encounters’:

acts of misreading or misinterpretation, renegacy and apostasy of large

sections of an erstwhile Marxisant generation, overdetermination by chang-

ing political conjunctures.

91

They also possessed intellectual conditions of

possibility, or, in non-transcendental terms, they were effects whose causes

must be searched for among the elements of the original Althusserian syn-

thesis itself. This is not to argue, in Hegelian fashion, that these developments

should be regarded as the ‘truth of’ the Althusserian system. Rather, it is

to follow Althusser himself when, in a Spinozist reversal of the Hegelian

106 • Peter Thomas

90

Althusser 1997, p. 11.

91

A full account of these confused knowledge s should include not only the

well-known move towards a nebulous post-Marxism by some former Althusserians
(most notably, Hindess and Hirst, Laclau and Mouffe), nor only the role played by
the Althusserian formation in the more general transitional process of Marxism
to postmodernism in the academy, but also the fate of the reception of Althusser in
the wider intellectual and political culture, particularly as a complex element in the
complex and uneven world-wide process of Communist parties’ de-Stalinisation
throughout the 1970s and early 1980s. The role of Althusserianism in this last pro-
cess is a feature which remains under-explored in recent assessments of the Althus-
serian legacy. An important political discussion of the reception of Althusser ’s
work in Australia and its journey from oppositional political formation to academic
orthodoxy can be found in Althofer 1999.

background image

telos, he argued that ‘the truth of a philosophy lies entirely in its effects’.

92

If

the potentially negative consequences which I shall outline remained only

potential in Althusser’s own work, and are therefore, as Michael Sprinker

noted, ‘outcomes for which Althusser cannot be held solely responsible’, it

remains an historical fact that they were developments which ‘his writings

did certainly help to license’, whether these were based upon a faithful read-

ing of the original texts or not.

93

Two important potential consequences

of Spinoza’s and Althusser’s critiques can be contrasted in support of this

contention that Althusser’s and Spinoza’s respective totalities are incom-

mensurable. If they appear to repeat well-known objections to Althusser’s

thought, it is hoped that their ‘theoretical’ rather than ‘polemical’ treatment

will allow a more balanced judgement and understanding of the causes

and effects of both Althusser’s work and that of his (more or less faithful)

followers. Further, it is hoped that they will furnish preliminary theses

for future research into the legitimate and illegitimate possible modes of

appropriation of Spinoza by contemporary Marxism.

First, because Spinoza’s Deus sive Natura was an inŽnite totality, its power

was not exhausted by enumerating the various phenomena perceivable by

the human intellect. In other words, it was not the sum of its parts. Human

practices, like all Žnite entities, were particular Žnite modiŽcations of the one

substance, conceived through one of its different attributes, dependent upon

the one substance for their Being. But Deus sive Natura’s integrity and potency
derived not from these modiŽcations, but from itself as the cause of itself

[causa sui]. A social totality, on the other hand, does not possess the same
type of objectivity, nor the same relationship to the phenomena which occur

within it. It possesses no being independent of the particular humans prac-

tices which occur within it, nor does it continue to exist, once those practices

themselves have ceased to exist – in a strict sense, it is the sum total of

its parts. To posit a social totality as bearing to its parts the same causal

relationship as that of Spinoza’s one substance to its modiŽcations risks

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 107

92

Althusser 1997, p. 4. Montag makes the same point in relation to the Tractatus

Theologico-Politicus: ‘As Spinoza remarked of Scripture, a text is to be judged sacred
or profane, good or evil, not by virtue of what it says, or even its truth, but by
its power to move people to mutual love and support. A philosophical work is
thus always an intervention in a concrete situation and is to be judged by the effects
it produces in this situation.’ (Montag 1998, p. xi).

93

Sprinker 1995, p. 203.

background image

effacing this important distinction. It disregards the speciŽc ontology

appropriate to a social totality and establishes it as a natural formation

in-and-for-itself, i.e. as possessing a being independent from the human activ-

ities which occur within it. This, in effect, was one of the central objections

raised by Althusser’s opponents to his vision of a structure of structures in

which humans were the mere Träger of structural determinations. In polemi-
cising against ‘organicist’ notions of human agency, it seemed to some critics

that Althusser had, instead, naturalised the social totality. It was no longer a

consequence of human practices, but an objective structure which preceded,

determined and existed independently of them. From the emphasis of pre-

vious Marxism on the social totality being a Kampfplatz of contradictory class
interests, capitalism now seemed to have become a thing, a great Leviathan

brooding over a world which could expect no delivery from its potentate’s

régime.

Second, Spinoza’s refusal to regard the cause of the one substance as

separate from its effects (as did the notion a creator) required him to refute

the complementary notion that there remained potentials of God’s power

yet to be actualised (providence, or a divine plan). Such a notion supposes

a limitation upon God’s power, or a deŽciency in his being,

94

a situation which

is inconceivable for an absolutely inŽnite being whose essence coincides with

his existence.

95

Deus sive Natura was already given in its inŽnity. As Spinoza

argued in the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, ‘nature . . . always observes laws

and rules which involve eternal necessity and truth, although they may not

all be known to us, and therefore she keeps a Žxed and immutable order’.

96

It was this proposition which enabled Spinoza to attempt rationally to under-

stand the necessary order of determinations which obtained within the

one substance, viewing them as if from the standpoint of eternity [sub specie
aeternitatis
], rather than by taking ‘refuge in the will of God, that is, the

sanctuary of ignorance’.

97

The attempt to comprehend a social totality, on the

108 • Peter Thomas

94

EIApp: ‘if God acts for the sake of an end, he necessarily wants something which

he lacks’.

95

EIDi: ‘By cause of itself I understand that whose essence involves existence, or

that whose nature cannot be conceived except as existing.’ EIP11: ‘God, or a substance
consisting of inŽnite attributes, each of which expresses eternal and inŽnite essence,
necessarily exists.’

96

Spinoza 1951, p. 83.

97

EIApp.

background image

other hand, cannot assume any such plenitude of being. A social totality is

necessarily incomplete, subject to further development and transformation

by the human practices which comprise it, which may possibly, but not

necessarily, involve the realisation of still dormant potentials. Furthermore,

because ‘reection on the forms of human life . . . begins post festum’,

98

the

concept of a social totality must always be provisional. Future social forma-

tions, comprising different practices and relationships, may make possible

conceptions of the social whole radically at odds with those produced in our

own epoch, not only in terms of its content, but also of its structure. This is
another way of saying that, because the concept of a social totality is one

of those ‘forms of thought which are socially valid, and therefore objective,

for the relations of production belonging to this historically determined

mode of social production’,

99

it necessarily is modelled, in our own time,

on the practices of a capitalist mode of production and its social relations.

To efface this concrete determinant by analysing the social totality as if it
were Spinoza’s one substance, however, risks positing, as having a validity

for social totalities in general, both contents and a structure which are speciŽc
to capitalist social relations and their comprehension in the notion of a

(capitalist) social totality. The Žnite secretly becomes the model for the inŽnite,

in much the same way as Spinoza argued had been done by the notion that

the divine possessed the human features of an appetite, will and desire. In

effect, these were the charges brought by many of Althusser’s critics: that

he was covertly projecting the historically speciŽc features of capitalism

onto the notion of a social totality in general (particularly in relation to one

interpretation of his theory of the eternity of ideology), and that the social

totality had become a self-contained, unfractured plane of self-afŽrming,

mutually reinforcing elements and levels to which there was literally

no exterior, not even socialism. ‘The bourgeoisie can be overthrown; the

ascendancy of structural causality is without term’, in the words of Gregory

Elliott’s succinct summary – which left some critics questioning if even the

Žrst possibility would be realised.

100

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 109

98

Marx 1976, p. 168.

99

Marx 1976, p. 169.

100

Elliott 1987, pp. 174–5.

background image

Conclusion

The conclusion to be drawn from this brief consideration of the differences

between Althusser ’s and Spinoza’s critiques is not the restoration of the

Andersonian thesis that Marxists must vigilantly guard against the corruption

of their creed by foreign elements drawn from pre-Marxian metaphysics.

Rather, it is that attempts to reinvigorate contemporary historical material-

ism by drawing upon elements of previous philosophies (or, equally, the

attempt to judge such efforts) will only be successful if they are undertaken

with a full and vigilant consciousness of the historical determinateness of

thought and philosophy. This is merely to restate a thesis which has always

been the foundation of the Marxist approach to the history of ideas, succinctly

encapsulated in a maxim of Fredric Jameson: ‘Always historicise!’

As I have previously noted, one of the distinguishing features of the Marxist

Spinozisms subsequent to and in part inspired by Althusser ’s (such as

Macherey’s, Balibar’s, Negri’s, Tosel’s, Montag’s and others collected in the

volume The New Spinoza) has been precisely such an attempt to produce a
more historically satisfying account of our contemporary relation to Spinoza’s

thought. An assessment of these works and their success in avoiding the

negative consequences which I have argued accompanied Althusser’s detour

via Spinoza will form the subject of a future study. I have dealt at such

length in this study with Anderson’s judgement of the nature of Althusser’s

Spinozism, however, in order to open the space necessary for a fuller and

unprejudiced engagement with these works and Spinoza’s thought more

generally. Given the richness of these works and their exploration of some

of the fundamental philosophical concepts of the Marxist tradition, I believe

that such an engagement is one of the pressing tasks for Anglophone Marxism,

in both its theoretical and activist forms. Whatever the errors or failings in

his initial attempt, Althusser should be remembered as the Žgure who more

than any other made these researches possible, which is, Žnally, to recover

another ‘effect’ or ‘truth’ of the Althusserian moment as an important resource

for the contemporary revitalisation of Marxism.

110 • Peter Thomas

background image

References

Althofer, Jayson 1999, ‘Activist and Theoretical Marxisms: Early Receptions of Althusser

in Australia’, Overland, 155: 56–61.

Althusser, Louis 1976, Essays in Self Criticism, London: NLB.

Althusser, Louis 1977, For Marx, trans. Ben Brewster, London: NLB.

Althusser, Louis 1994, The Future Lasts a Long Time, trans. Richard Veasey, London:

Vintage.

Althusser, Louis 1997, ‘The Only Materialist Tradition, Part 1: Spinoza’, in Montag

and Stolze (eds.) 1997.

Althusser, Louis and Étienne Balibar 1970, Reading Capital, trans. Ben Brewster, London:

NLB.

Anderson, Perry 1976, Considerations on Western Marxism, London: NLB.

Anderson, Perry 1980, Arguments Within English Marxism, London: Verso.

Balibar, Étienne 1998, Spinoza and Politics, trans. Peter Snowden, London: Verso.

Benjamin, Walter 1970, Illuminations, trans. Harry Zohn, Glasgow: Fontana.

Clarke, Simon, Terry Lovell, et al. (eds.) 1980, One-Dimensional Marxism: Althusser and

the Politics of Culture, London: Allison & Busby.

Colletti, Lucio 1972, From Rousseau to Lenin, trans. John Merrington and Judith White,

London: NLB.

Collier, Andrew 1989, ScientiŽc Realism and Socialist Thought, Hemel Hempstead:

Harvester Wheatsheaf.

Eagleton, Terry 1991, Ideology, London: Verso.

Elliott, Gregory 1987, The Detour of Theory, London: Verso.

Elliott, Gregory (ed.) 1994, Althusser: A Critical Reader, Oxford: Blackwell.

Foucault, Michel 1970, The Order of Things, New York: Vintage.

Hegel, Georg W.F. 1995, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, trans. E.S. Haldane, Lincoln:

Nebraska University Press.

Jameson, Fredric 1981, The Political Unconscious, London: Methuen.

Jay, Martin 1984, Marxism and Totality. Cambridge: Polity.

Kaplan, E. Ann and Michael Sprinker (eds.) 1993, The Althusserian Legacy, London:

Verso.

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 111

background image

Lenin, Vladimir I. 1950, ‘Left-Wing’ Communism, an Infantile Disorder, Moscow: Foreign

Languages Press.

Lenin, Vladimir I.1961, Philosophical Notebooks, Moscow: Foreign Languages Press.

Macherey, Pierre 1998, In a Materialist Way: Selected Essays, edited by Warren Montag,

trans. Ted Stolze, London: Verso.

Marx, Karl 1973, Grundrisse, trans. Martin Nicolaus, Harmondsworth: Penguin.

Marx, Karl 1974, Early Writings, trans. Rodney Livingstone & Gregor Benton,

Harmondsworth: Penguin.

Marx, Karl 1976, Capital, Volume I, Harmondsworth: Penguin.

Marx, Karl and Frederick Engels 1975, Collected Works, Volume 1, London: Lawrence

and Wishart.

Marx, Karl and Frederick Engels 1976, The German Ideology, Moscow: Progress Publishers.

Montag, Warren 1993, ‘Spinoza and Althusser Against Hermeneutics: Interpretation

or Intervention?’, in Kaplan & Sprinker (eds.) 1993.

Montag, Warren 1998, ‘Preface’, in Balibar 1998.

Montag, Warren 1999, Bodies, Masses, Power: Spinoza and His Contemporaries, London,

Verso.

Montag, Warren & Ted Stolze (eds.) 1997, The New Spinoza, Minneapolis: University

of Minnesota Press.

Negri, Antonio 1991, The Savage Anomaly: The Power of Spinoza’s Metaphysics and Politics,

trans. Michael Hardt, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.

New Left Review (eds.) 1977, Western Marxism: A Critical Reader, London: Verso.

Norris, Christopher 1991, Spinoza and the Origins of Modern Critical Theory, Oxford:

Blackwell.

Smith, Steven B. 1984, Reading Althusser: An Essay on Structural Marxism, Ithaca: Cornell

University Press.

Spinoza, Benedict 1951, A Theologico-Political Treatise and A Political Treatise, trans.

R.H.M. Elwes, New York: Dover.

Spinoza, Benedict 1985, Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione, in The Collected Works of

Spinoza, Volume 1, Edwin Curley (trans. and ed.), Princeton: Princeton University

Press.

112 • Peter Thomas

background image

Spinoza, Benedict 1994, Ethics, trans. Edwin Curley, Harmondsworth: Penguin.

Sprinker, Michael 1995, ‘The Legacies of Althusser ’, Yale French Studies, 88: 201–25.

Thompson, Edward P. 1978, The Poverty of Theory & Other Essays, London: Merlin.

Tosel, André 1997, ‘Superstition and Reading’, in Montag and Stolze (eds.) 1997.

Wood, Ellen Meiksins 1986, The Retreat from Class: A New True Socialism, London: Verso.

Yovel, Yirmiyahu 1989, Spinoza and Other Heretics, Princeton: Princeton University

Press.

Philosophical Strategies: Althusser and Spinoza • 113


Wyszukiwarka

Podobne podstrony:
student sheet activity 6 e28093 strategy mood and tone
Trading Setups Review Trading Strategies, Guides, and Articles for Active Tech
The History Of Philosophy Chapter 3, Aristotle and the End of Classical Greek Philosophy
Current Clinical Strategies, History and Physical Exam in Medicine (2005) 10Ed; BM OCR 7 0 2 5
Philosophy of action and theory of narrative
Marketer s Toolkit (09) Pricing It Right Strategies, Applications, And Pitfalls(Harvard Business S
My Personal Philosophy of Teaching and Learning
The History Of Philosophy Chapter 7, Indian and Islamic philosophy
social capital strategic relatedness and the formation of intraorganizational likages
cognitive change strategic action and organizational renewal
Pearson (Maimonides and Spinoza) BB
Go (Weiqi) Philosophy And Playing Strategies
Lloyd, Routledge philosophy guidebook to Spinoza and the Ethics (IN) BB
Essay on Spinoza Ironist and Moral Philosopher
IR and philosophy of history
Mettern S P Rome and the Enemy Imperial Strategy in the Principate
Functional Origins of Religious Concepts Ontological and Strategic Selection in Evolved Minds
isaf stratcom strategy ends ways and means 2008
Pappas; Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Plato and the Republic

więcej podobnych podstron