KATOLICKI UNIWERSYTET LUBELSKI
JANA PAWŁA II
Wydział Nauk Humanistycznych
Instytut Filologii Angielskiej
Agata Bednarz
nr albumu: 81874
THE STRUCTURE OF DP IN ENGLISH AND POLISH
Praca magisterska
napisana pod kierunkiem
dr hab. Anny Bondaruk, prof. KUL
w Katedrze
Językoznawstwa Teoretycznego
Lublin 2010
2
CONTENTS
List of abbreviations ……..………………………………………………………… 4
Introduction ..………………………………………………………………………. 6
Chapter 1: The DP Hypothesis- Theoretical Background
Introduction…………………………………………………………………….. 9
1.1. The GB analysis of an NP and a clause ...……………………………... 9
1.2. Abney’s DP Hypothesis ...……………………………………………... 16
1.3. Further remarks on the structure of nominal phrases ..……….…….….. 24
Conclusion ..………………………………………………………………… 28
Chapter 2: Functional Projections within the DP
Introduction ……………………………………………………………………. 29
2.1. AgrP - Agreement Phrase ……………………………………………… 30
2.2. NumP – Number Phrase ……………………………………………….. 34
2.3. QP – Quantifier Phrase ……………………………………………….... 36
2.4. The order of adjectives …………………………………………………. 42
2.5. Little n – the nominal shell ………………………………………… …. 45
2.6. DemP – Demonstrative Phrase and PossP – Possessive Phrase ……….. 48
2.7. The hierarchy of functional elements within the DP …………………... 51
Conclusion ……………………………………………………………………... 55
Chapter 3: The DP in Polish
Introduction ……………………………………………………………………. 57
3.1. Is there a DP in Polish? ………………………………………………... 58
3.1.1. Left Branch Extraction (LBE) …………………………………... 59
3.1.2. Double genitive constructions …………………………………... 65
3.1.3. The lack of N-to-D movement …………………………………. .. 66
3.1.4. Other arguments against the DP analysis of Polish nominals …... 68
3
3.2. The internal structure of nominal phrases in Polish …………………… 70
3.2.1. Noun – pronoun asymmetry. The position of personal pronouns .. 71
3.2.2. Adjectives ……………………………………………………...... 73
3.2.3. Possessive and demonstrative pronouns ………………………… 77
3.3. The structure of Polish nominal phrases ………………………….......... 79
Conclusion ……………………………………………………………………... 81
Summary and conclusions ………………………………………………………... ... 83
References ………………………………………………………………………....... 88
4
List of Abbreviations
1
st
– first person
2
nd
– second person
3
rd
– third person
A – Adjective
ACC – accusative
Agr – Agreement
AgrP – Agreement Phrase
AP – Adjective Phrase
AUX – auxiliary
C – Complementizer
Class – Classification
ClassP – Classification Phras
Conj – Conjunction
ConjP – Conjunction Phrase
CP – Complementiser Phrase
D – Determiner
DAT – dative
def. – definite
Deg – Degree
DegP – Degree Phrase
Dem – Demonstrative
DemP – demonstrative Phrase
Det – Determiner
DP – Determiner Phrase
ERG – Ergative
EPP – Extended Projection Principle
fem. – feminine
Foc – Focus
FocP – Focus Phrase
GB Theory – the Government and
Binding Theory
GEN – genitive
I – Inflection
IP – Inflection Phrase
K – nominal complementizer
KP – nominal complementizer phrasal
projection
LBE – the Left Branch Extraction
masc. – masculine
n – light noun
N – Noun
NP – Noun Phrase
NOM – nominative
nP – light noun phrase
Num – Number
NumP – Number Phrase
Ø – empty position
Ɵ-role – theta- or thematic role
P – Preposition
pl. – plural
PP – Preposition Phrase
possd – Possessed feature
Q – Quantifier
QP – Quantifier Phrase
sing. – singular
5
Spec. – Specifier
Subj. – subjective
t – trace
Tns. – Tense
UTAH – the Uniormity of Theta Assignment Hypothesis
v – light verb
V – Verb
vP – light verb phrase
VP – Verb Phrase
X – any lexical category
XP – any phrasal category
6
Introduction
The aim of this dissertation is to investigate the structure of nominal expressions
in English and Polish. The thesis examines the syntax of nominal expressions in both
languages and aims at providing a universal representation of nominal phrases. The
starting point for the study is the DP Hypothesis put forward by Abney (1987).
The nominal expression investigated in this dissertation is a constituent headed
by a Noun. Some examples are given in (1) below:
(1) a. Mary is a student.
b. This is a big black dog.
c. The existence of DP in articleless languages is controversial.
All the expressions in italics given in (1) belong to a group of nominal phrases.
Although they differ in the degree of complexity, they all share the same syntactic
structure. Following Abney (1987), it is claimed that they are all instantiations of a
Determiner Phrase (DP). They are headed by a functional element D, whose overt
realisation corresponds to either a definite or an indefinite article (in English those are:
a(n)/ the).
Postulating the universality of grammar, it appears necessary to assume that the
same structure applies to all human languages, whether they show some overt
realisation of D or not.
However, a lot of controversies surround the structure of DP. Some of the
queries are listed below:
1. Are nominal expressions consisting of only one word DPs? (e.g. Mary)
7
2. If an article or an empty element constitutes a head of the phrase, what is the
syntactic position of other elements appearing within the phrase, i.e.
Quantifiers, Adjectives, etc.?
3. Why do articleless languages allow syntactic phenomena (e.g. Left Branch
Extraction) disallowed by languages with overt realisations of D?
Those questions and others have been addressed by numerous studies carried on
since the DP Hypothesis first appeared. Data taken from different languages and
different elements of nominal expressions were targeted. However, it is possible to
distinguish two major stands: one extending the DP Hypothesis onto all languages
without exceptions (Abney (1987), Progovac (1998), Migdalski (2000), Sio (2006),
Rutkowski (2000, 2002a, 2002b, 2002c, 2007a, 2007b, 2009), among others), the other
treating the nominals appearing in aricleless languages as traditional NPs (Fukui (1986),
Chierchia (1998), Willim (2000), Kim (2004), Bošković (2003, 2004, 2005, 2008),
among others).
As far as the theoretical model is concerned, this study is based on two linguistic
theories created by Chomsky, i.e. the Government and Binding Theory (Chomsky
(1981)) and the Minimalist Program (Chomsky (2000, 2001)). The lack of a single
framework stems from the fact that a considerable number of important studies on the
structure of nominals has not been carried out with the recently recognised Minimalist
Program, for instance, two works crucial for this study: Abney’s (1987) The English
noun phrase in its sentential aspekt and Rutkowski’s (2007b) Hipoteza frazy
przedimkowej jako narzedzie opisu składniowego polskich grup imiennych.
This dissertation offers an overview of the DP Hypothesis, as well as more
recent interpretations of the structure of nominal expressions. Both approaches toward
8
articleless languages are taken into consideration. Chapter 1focusses on Abney’s (1987)
dissertation, which introduces the idea of DP structure. The goal of this chapter is to
present the DP Hypothesis, all together with its theoretical background. Furthermore,
early analyses of functional projections intervening between a DP and an NP are
outlined and explained.
Chapter 2 provides a survey of more recent approaches to the DP structure. The
major part of this chapter is devoted to various functional projections appearing
between a DP and an NP. This analysis leads to postulating a complete structure of
nominal phrases, which can be applied both to the English and Polish language.
The final chapter focuses on the analysis of the structure of Polish nominals. It
presents two recent approaches to nominal phrases in Slavic languages: one adapting
Abney’s DP Hypothesis to the Polish syntax, the other presenting Polish nominals as
NPs. Taking both approaches into consideration, the structure worked out in the
previous chapter of the study is explained and special attention is paid to the possibility
of adapting it to the Polish syntax. Finally, the complete structure of a DP in Polish is
presented.
9
Chapter 1
The DP Hypothesis - Theoretical Background
Introduction
The aim of Chapter 1 is to introduce the background and core assumptions of the DP
Hypothesis introduced by Stephen Abney in his PhD dissertation, in 1987. On the basis
of cross-linguistic indicators and facts, Abney demonstrates that the classical GB
interpretation of the structure of nominal phrases is flawed. He rejects the idea of a
nominal phrase understood as a phrasal projection of a lexical head – a Noun, and
suggests a new structure – one parallel to the structure of a clause and based on the
functional projection of a Determiner with an NP functioning as its complement.
The basic GB analysis of the structure of nominal phrases, together with syntactic
facts suggesting its explanatory inadequacy is given in section 1. Subsequently, section
2 outlines Abney’s DP Hypothesis, the way it is presented in his PhD dissertation.
Finally, section 3 focuses on further problems with the structure of nominal phrases,
especially concentrating on the position of elements intervening between a Determiner
and a Noun, i.e. Quantifiers, Adjectives, etc.
1.1 The GB analysis of an NP and a clause
The classical GB interpretation of the structure of nominal phrases provides us with
the following phrase maker:
10
(1) NP
D(P) N’
N
XP
As can be seen in (1), the maximal projection of a nominal phrase, the NP,
dominates the intermediate projection N’ and the specifier D(P), the Determiner
(Phrase). The N’, in turn, dominates the zero projection, i.e. the Noun (N) and its
complement, marked as an XP in order to show that it can be realised syntactically by
various types of phrases, for instance PPs.
This structure is built in accordance with the X-bar Theory (Chomsky (1970);
Jackendoff (1977)). The phrase is endocentric – the constituents are projections of a
single head. It observes the Binary Branching Constraint – the higher nodes dominate
only two nodes at once – and the Singlemotherhood Constraint – nodes are dominated
only by one element at the same time.
However, that structure raises numerous questions. The basic one concernes the
status of Determiners. In English, all the elements that may appear under D, i.e.
possessives (possessive pronouns and genitives), demonstratives and articles, remain in
complementary distribution – they cannot co-occur within one phrase, as shown in (2).
(2) a. *the Mary’s description
b. *the her description
c. *Mary’s her description
d. *this the description
(Haegeman and Guéron (1999: 408))
e. this description
f. her description
g. Mary’s description
h. the description
11
The conclusion to be drawn from (2 a-h) is that all Determiners occupy the same
node – D. No clear evidence pointing to the possibility of claiming the existence of the
DP can be found – this fact is reflected by the presence of brackets, which are used to
mark optionality, within the DP in the phrase maker in (1). However, to accept the
possibility that Determiner Phrases do not exist is to accept a strong violation of the X-
bar Theory constraints, which also means accepting the fact that Determiners, as a class,
are possibly not able to project further, take complements or to have proper specifiers. If
this were so, Determiners would be the only exception within all lexical and functional
elements of a language.
What is more, the claim that all elements, traditionally bearing the name of
Determiners, share the same grammatical features turns out not to be true when
confronted with the data in (3a) and (3b) below:
(3) a. Mary’s house
b. the house
my teacher’s house
a house
the woman next door’s house
Ø houses
the French student’s house
this house
the teacher of history’s house
that house
her house
these houses
Thelma and Louise’s house
those houses
(Haegeman and Guéron (1999: 409))
As demonstrated in (3a), possessors are an open class of elements; they are
unlimited and new elements within this class can still appear. On the contrary, articles
and demonstratives, as can be seen in (3b), constitute a closed class – no new elements
can be created. This argument is true cross-linguistically – the restriction with regard to
the number of articles and demonstratives is evident in other languages as well, not only
in English. For instance, in Hungarian there is only one definite article a (Szabolcsi
(1984)). What is more, in comparison with the possessives, articles and demonstratives
12
do not contribute significantly to the descriptive content of the phrase. Articles carry the
[±definiteness] feature, whereas demonstratives indicate the spatial relation between the
speaker and the object being described (Haegeman and Guéron (1999: 410)).
It is also worth noticing that not all languages have a restriction on the co-
occurrencee of possessives and articles or demonstratives, as presented in (4).
(4) a. un mio libro
[Italian]
a my book
‘a book of mine’
b. esas ideas tuyas
[Spanish]
those ideas yours
‘those ideas of yours’
c. cartea ta
[Romance]
(Radford (1988: 171-172))
book-def. your
‘the book of yours’`
d. ten mój pies
[Polish]
this my dog
‘this dog of mine’
The constructions shown in (4) are ungrammatical in English but they are fully
grammatical in Romance and Slavic languages. A possible explanation for this
phenomenon is offered by Radford (1988). He suggests that Determiners can be
attached to the maximal projection of NP and they extend an NP into another NP. This
hypothetical structure is presented in (5) below:
(5) a.
NP
b. NP→ D NP
D
NP
D
NP
13
On the basis of the structure in (5a), it is possible to formulate a phrase structure rule
presented in (5b), saying that an NP immediately dominates a Determiner and another
NP. This is strongly criticised by Radford (1988). A major flaw of this line of reasoning
is that it does not take into consideration the fact that rule (5b) is recursive and hence
can be reapplied indefinitely many times. In accordance with rule (5b), the structures
presented in (6) below would be recognised as grammatical.
(6) a. *the a this my car
b. *mój ten wasz tamten stół
[Polish]
*my this your that table
c. *un mio tuo quello libro
[Italian]
*a my your this book
As can be seen in (6a-c ), a larger number of Determiners within one nominal
phrase is ungrammatical even in Romance or Slavic languages, in spite of the fact that
these languages normally allow the combination of a possessor plus an article or a
demonstrative.
Analysing the notion of multiple determiners presented above, a conclusion may
be drawn that possessors constitute a class of elements different from articles and
demonstratives and, because of this, they need to have a separate position assigned to
them within the construction of a nominal phrase (Haegeman and Guéron (1999)). This
position seems to be missing in the classical structure that treats nominal phrases simply
as NPs with Determiners occupying the position of [Spec; NP].
Further evidence against the structure in (1) stems from a comparison of Nouns
and Verbs understood as two most important lexical classes. In contradistinction to the
questionable structure of a nominal phrase, the GB Theory provides us with a complete
14
and in-depth analysis of verbal phrases. Verbs (and Nouns alike) project maximal
projections – Verb Phrases (VPs) but, above all, they are augmented with functional
projections of an Inflection and a Complementiser. Therefore, the entire clause is
understood as an extended projection of a Verb. This structure is presented in (7).
(7) CP
Spec
C’
C
IP
NP
I’
I
VP
[± tense]
[±agreement] Specifier V’
(Haegeman (1997:18))
V
XP
As can be seen, each lexical or functional element within a clause projects its
intermediate and maximal projection in accordance with the X-bar Theory. The highest
projection of the clause is the CP – the Complementiser Phrase, that dominates its
specifier and C’. The CP is headed by a Complementiser, which carries the illocutionary
force of the sentence and takes the IP – the Inflection Phrase as its complement. The IP
immediately dominates the NP (which fulfils the role of the subject of the clause) and
I’. The I’ dominates the head of the IP. I is the functional element carrying the features
[± tense; ±agreement]. The complement of I is the Verb Phrase –VP, which
immediately dominates its specifier and V.’ VP is headed by a Verb which can take
numerous possible types of complements (for instance: PPs, NPs, CPs, etc.).
The complexity of the structure presented in (8) is even more striking when we
consider the following facts revealing the similarities between nominal and verbal
15
phrases that cannot be explained with the help of the structure in (1). First of all,
Determiners show some features similar to Complementisers (Haegeman and Guéron
(1999)). They constitute a closed class of functional elements and they do not contribute
significantly to the semantics of the sentence. Still, they can introduce the Noun Phrase
and have the [±definiteness] or [±distance] feature.
In addition, there appears another question, this time, based on the analysis of the
semantic projection of a Verb Phrase and a Noun Phrase. According to Chomsky
(1957), each lexical item has its categorial (c-) and semantic (s-) projection. The two c-
projections are an X-bar and an X-double-bar projections of the syntactic unit and the s-
projection is a projection of the meaning of the lexical item. It is worth focusing on the
fact that the s-projection of a verb spreads over the best part of the sentence involving
all of its main elements, i.e. the subject, the predicate and the objects. To put it another
way, the whole clause refers to the action denoted by the verb, other parts of the
sentence, e.g. adverbials, just give some additional information. By way of illustration,
in John is doing homework, the whole clause expresses an action of doing homework.
Here homework constitutes a complement of the verb, whereas John (Specifier of IP)
adds the information about who the Agent is.
In contradistinction to a Verb, a Noun has a narrower-spread s-projection – it is
simply the same as the c-projection of the noun (i.e. NP). Therefore, it affects only
complements enclosed within the NP.
16
1.2 Abney’s DP Hypothesis
The starting point for Abney’s dissertation is an ambiguous construction that could
be understood both as an NP and a clause (Abney (1987: 14-15)). An example of this
construction is shown in (8) below:
(8)
John’s building a spaceship.
That can be paraphrased as follows:
(9) John built a spaceship.
With the meaning illustrated in (9) the structure constitutes the so-called
‘Poss- ing’ gerundive construction, which in its form is similar to a clause, yet it
remains an NP. From the comparison of (8) and the corresponding clause (9) one
may draw the following conclusions, which may later on serve as evidence for the
theory assuming the existence of DPs:
1. The structure of (8) is similar to the structure of (9): John is a subject, building
denotes the action, therefore fulfils the same function as a verb, and a spaceship
is an object.
2. (8), in contrast to (9), is an NP because it has the characteristic distribution of
NPs, i.e. it can function as a [Spec; IP], compare the following examples (Abney
(1987: 15)):
(10) a. *Did [that John built a spaceship] upset you?
b. Did [John’s building a spaceship] upset you?
c. Did [John] upset you?
Putting these two pieces of information together, we obtain a structure as presented
in the P-maker below:
17
(11)
NP
.
NP
VP
John’s
V
NP
building a spaceship
Here the NP John's building a spaceship comprises an NP John’s in the position of
[Spec; NP] and its verbal complement building a spaceship. However, this structure
represents a strong violation of basic conditions on syntactic structure of phrases. First
of all, the Endocentricity Constraint is violated by the fact that the highest NP lacks a
head. Secondly, the structure of NPs John’s and a spaceship is still unclear.
Abney’s solution to this problem is as follows: the structure of noun phrases must be
based on the structure of clauses and it must be headed by an inflectional element. As a
result of this, the Endocentricity Constraint is satisfied and the presence of an overt
gerundive ending ’s is accounted for. The P-maker of an NP structure showing the
similarity to a clause is given in (12b) (Abney (1987:23)).
(12) a. Clause
b. Abney’s nominal phrase
IP
XP
NP
I’
XP
X’
John
John’s
I
VP
X
VP
[Tns, Agr]
[Agr]
V
NP
V
NP
built a spaceship
building a spaceship
18
The head of the nominal phrase is a functional element represented by Agreement
(it has no name by itself because its functions are still not clarified, therefore it remains
marked as an X). The VP building a spaceship is its complement, and John's (another
nominal expression) functions as its Specifier. This structure can be confirmed by
examples from Turkish, especially as far as the inflectional projection hosting Agr is
concerned:
(13) a. el
b. sen-in el-in
c. on-un el-i
you- Gen hand- 2
nd
sg
he-Gen hand-3
rd
sg
‘the/a hand’
‘your hand’
‘his hand’
(Abney (1987:21))
In the examples above a noun acquires the same number and person as the
possessive pronoun preceding it. This strong agreement between the possessor and the
noun in Turkish serves as an argument for the presence of an Agr within the noun
phrase. The logical consequence of this postulate and the fact that within clauses the
Agr feature, always carried by the functional element (I), is required by a functional
element present within an NP and similar to the I.
The idea of the inflectional projection within the noun phrase seems even more
unavoidable in the case of languages like Yup’ik, in which the subject of a noun phrase
is assigned the same Ergative case as the subject of a clause.
(14) a. angute-t kiputa- a- t
the men- Erg buy- Past- it- 3
rd
pl masc
‘the men bought it’
b. angute- t kuiga- t
the men- Erg river- 3
rd
pl masc
‘the men’s river’
(Abney (1987: 39))
19
According to Abney (1987), the mysterious element similar to I and carrying the
Agr feature is in fact a Determiner (D) projecting into a D’ and further on into a DP. His
arguments supporting this hypothesis are as follows (Abney (1987: 75-76)):
1. Determiners are a class of functional elements, therefore they can behave
like modals (which appear under I in IPs) and appear under functional D.
What is more, they are the best candidate for being a carrier of the Agr
feature, similarly to the Inflection within a clause.
2. With the hypothesis applied, it is finally possible to distinguish the
intermediate and maximal projections and pinpoint specifiers and
complements taken by Determiners. As a result, Determiners, as a class, are
no longer defective with respect to the X’- theory.
The representation of this new structure of nominal phrases is shown in the P-
maker below:
(15)
DP
.
DP
D’
John’s
D
VP
Agr
V
NP
building a spaceship
The nominal phrase is presented as a DP headed by a functional D filled by the
Agr. The main DP takes its own specifier and the complement, i.e. the DP John's and
the VP building a spaceship, respectively, this structure works for any kind of nominal
20
expression in English. The space for all pre-nominal elements is provided, and the
presence of Agreement is accounted for and shown within the structure below:
(16)
DP
D’
DP
D
NP
a.
my
Agr
pen
b.
Ø
a
cat
It also accounts for double-modifier structures combining an article with a
possessor (i.e. multiple modifiers presented already on the basis of examples taken from
Romance and Slavic languages in section 1.2. of this chapter), which appear also in
Hungarian. There, the possessor, a determiner, is preceded by another determiner - the
definite article a/az, e.g.
(17) a. Az en vendeg-e-m
the my guest- possd-1
st
sg
‘my quest’
b. a te ismerös- ei- d
the your acquaintance-possd-2
nd
sg
‘your acquaintance’
(Abney (1987: 44))
Here the overt agreement between the possessor and the noun as well as the
appearance of multiple determiners (which were placed by Jackendoff (1977)) within a
treble- bar structure, violating basic constraints of the X-bar Theory) suggests that the
DP hypothesis is in fact true. Not only is there a need for a functional element that
would carry the agreement feature but also there must be a position for the possessive
pronoun that in classical interpretations filled the position of [Spec; NP], i.e.
Determiner. Following Szabolsci (1984), Abney claims that an additional determiner
21
like this appearing in Hungarian is a kind of complementiser K introducing noun
phrases instead of clauses
and projecting into K-bar and K-double-bar (Abney (1987:
44) after Szablocsi (1984)). This fact stresses still more strongly the sentential aspect of
nominal phrases. An example of a Hungarian phrase with a double-modifier and its P-
maker is shown in (18) (cf. (17a)).
(18) KP
K
DP
az
DP
i
D’
en
D
NP.
Agr
i
-m
N
N
j
Agr
j
vendeg- e-
(Abney (1987:44, 251))
What is also worth mentioning, Abney’s DP hypothesis allows us to locate PRO
in a subject position within the noun phrase. This ‘nominal’ PRO functions as an Agent
in cases like (19) below (Abney (1987:92)) e.g.
(19) [
DP
PRO the [
DP
destruction of the city]]
22
Here PRO is assigned a Θ-role via predication – PRO functions as an external argument
of destruction (reflecting the argument structure of clauses). What is more, PRO is also
responsible for licensing rationale clauses embedded within a noun phrase.
(20) the PRO review of the book [PRO to prove a point] (Abney (1987:93))
As can be seen in (20), only when PRO is present is the rationale clause
licensed, because the process of licensing requires the Agent Θ-role realized
syntactically and covert PRO can assume this role.
Another piece of evidence for Abney’s hypothesis is the notion of head to head
movement within the noun phrase, which accounts for post-nominal adjectives in
English. What is more, the NP-internal head-to-head movement reflects another
similarity between CPs and DPs. The head of the NP is claimed to move to the head of
the DP position (the equivalent of V-to- T and T- to- C movements). Due to this fact
adjectives appearing postnominally in English
are not exceptions any more but fit into a
general paradigm
(Abney (
1987: 287)).
(21)
a. a good boy
c. *good someone
b. *a boy good
d. someone good
According to Abney, someone like everyone, anyone, etc., represent
morphological mergers. Every and one are separately merged within an NP and they can
be formed thanks to the movement of one to the D position, which is illustrated in (22)
below:
23
(22)
DP
.
D
NP
D
N
AP
N’
some-one
i
good
N
t
i
In fact, not only have the concepts of PRO and head movement been affected by
the DP hypothesis, but above all, the notion of the determiner has undergone a great
change. Before 1987, the category of determiners included both possessors and articles.
However, after Abney’s dissertation, the status of possessors and pronouns has radically
changed. Abney claims that possessors cannot be determiners because:
1. possessors co-occur with other determiners therefore, they cannot occupy the
same place within the structure of the phrase (Abney (1987: 270)), e.g.
(23) a. in Italian:
un mio libro
‘a my book’
b. in Hungarian: az en ostalem
‘the my table’
2. possessors do not have the same distribution as DPs, as shown in (24):
(24) a. * the car of [Mark’s]
b. the car of [Mark]
c. [Mark’s] car (Abney (1987: 270))
On the contrary, pronouns are typical determiners:
1. pronouns do not occur with modifiers typical for NPs
(25) a. *Mark’s [you]
b. Mark’s [car] (Abney (1987: 281))
24
2. pronouns can appear with nouns within the so called idiosyncratic gaps, e.g.
(26) a. I Claudius
b. You fool
(Abney (1987: 282))
1.3 Further remarks on the structure of nominal phrases
Placing Determiners in the position of the head of a nominal phrase solves the main
problems that were left untouched by the traditional analysis of nominals. However,
there still remain queries left without answers, e.g. the question of the position of
elements intervening between Determiners and Nouns (written in italics) in (27) below.
(27) a. the many good man
(Abney (1987:290))
b. Ø two parts steel
c. Ø two dozen roses
d. Ø three men
(Abney (1987: 291))
The phrases presented above are the instances of a quantifier phrase - (27a), a
measure phrase - (27b), a semi-numeral phrase - (27c) and a numeral phrase - (27d).
They are all understood by Jackendoff (1977) as instances of treble-bar NPs, which are
unacceptable in the X-bar Theory. Abney’s (1987) answer to this problem is
proclaiming the existence of an additional projection appearing between a DP and an
NP, i.e. an AP (Adjective Phrase). Both structures - Jackendoff’s (28a) and Abney’s
(28b) - are shown below:
25
(28) a. N’’’
(Jackendoff (1977: 291))
b. DP
(Abney (1987:336))
Possr/D N’’
D AP
QP/NP
N’
DegP A’
two parts
two
N
A
NP
steel
parts
N
steel
In comparison with Jackendoff’s proposal in (28a), the structure offered by Abney in
(28b) shows the compliance with the X-bar Theory - no treble-bar projections are
involved. What is more, it provides us with a full structure with a place for an Adjective
Phrase.
Abney assumes that Quantifiers, Adverbs and descriptive Adjectives belong to a
single category of Adjectives (Abney (1987:293)) and that pre-nominal and post-
nominal Adjective Phrases differ in their inner structure and nature (Abney (1987:326)).
The first assumption stems from the following facts:
1. Quantifiers and Adjectives differ mostly in their semantics; the differences in
supporting the partitive constructions and functioning as pronouns do not
concern the comparative and superlative (Abney (1987:301)).
2. Adverbs and Adjectives take the same degree words and Adverbs as their
modifiers as shown in (29) (Abney (1987:301)). The ending -ly present with
Adverbs is just a prepositional adjective Case-marker and may be treated like
verbal ending -ing (Abney (1987:302) after Larson (1987)).
(29) a. sufficiently quick
b. sufficiently quickly
(Abney (1987: 301))
26
3. All Adjectives, Adverbs and Quantifiers share common [+N] feature (Abney
(1987:302)).
Therefore, adjective phrases, quantifier phrases and adverb phrases are identical
in their internal structure.
However, as has already been mentioned, there is a difference between pre-
nominal and post-nominal adjective phrases. According to Abney (1987), pre-nominal
adjective phrases are APs taking an NP as their complement, whereas post-nominal
adjective phrases are in truth Degree Phrases (DegPs).
As can be seen in (30) below, degree words within adjective phrases, e.g. too,
behave similarly to Determiners within nominal expressions. They modify all kinds of
adjective phrases appearing in the initial position, as in (30a) and (30b), and they cannot
be multiplied, as shown in (30c)
(30) a. too many
as hungrily
so long
b. too sick
as happy
c. *as too sick
*too as happy
Therefore, it is natural to claim that Degree words project DegPs and take
adjective phrases as complements, just like Determiners project DPs and take nominal
phrases as therir complements (Abney (1987: 298)). The structure of the DegP with
proper examples is presented by means of a P-maker in (31) below:
27
(31)
DegP
.
DegP
Deg’
Ø
AP
Deg AP
much [+Q]
too
tall
quite [+Adj] as nice
(Abney (1987:306))
As can be seen in (31), Abney’s proposal covers even adjective phrases which
function as modifiers of phrases like too tall that have already been recognized as
DegPs.
The case of pre-nominal adjective phrases is much different. First of all, pre-
nominal adjective phrases cannot take typical PP complements, whereas post nominal
DegPs must have complements, e.g.:
(32) a. the [proud] man
*the [proud of his son] man
b. *the man [proud]
the man [proud of his son]
(Abney (1987:326))
This query can be explained if we assume that instead of a typical PP the pre-
nominal AP takes an NP as its complement. At the same time, it appears that Adjectives
have similar properties to auxiliary verbs within verbal phrases, i.e. appearing as
‘auxiliaries’ they cannot take complements characteristic for their class and they f-select
NPs. Therefore, it is possible to claim that Adjectives are ‘defective’ Nouns, just as
corresponding Auxiliaries are defective Verbs (Abney (1987: 327)). This leads us to the
conclusion that the only structure possible for pre-nominal adjective phrases is the
structure presented in (28b).
28
Conclusion
In this chapter it has been shown that the classical GB structure of nominal phrases,
which treats them as NPs headed by a Noun with a Determiner in the [Spec; NP]
position is inadequate. In the case of Determiners, the GB analysis violates the
constraints of the X-bar theory. What is more, it fails to provide an appropriate
explanation for the cross-linguistic phenomenon of multiple determiners found in
languages of Romance and Slavic groups. In comparison with the structure of CPs, the
GB analysis of NPs ignores the similarities between Determiners and Complementisers,
which suggest that the former may fulfil the same function of introducing the
descriptive content of the phrase. In addition to this, the classical structure does not
explain the difference in understanding the s-projection of clauses and nominal phrases.
Abney’s (1987) proposal of analysing nominal phrases as DPs removes the
deficiencies of the former representation. It also accounts for the phenomena such as:
the argument structure of Poss-ing gerundive constructions, the strong agreement within
the nominal phrase, corresponding to the Inflection in clauses and post-nominal
adjectives in English. The explanation is offered also for the question concerning the
position of adjectives, quantifiers and other elements intervening between a Determiner
and a Noun, which according to Abney project their own projections (DegPs and APs).
29
Chapter 2
Functional projections within the DP
Introduction
In the first chapter, following Abney (1987), the existence of the Determiner Phrase has
been postulated as a functional projection built upon the Nominal Phrase. A nominal
phrase is headed by a functional element - D, just as a clause is headed by a functional
element I. However, aspiring to a uniformity between nominal and verbal structures,
motivated by the equal importance of both elements for the meaning of a sentence, we
are obliged to analyse the possibility of other functional projections existing within the
DP-projections intervening between the Determiner and its complement – NP, parallel
to projections appearing between an IP and an NP.
Chapter 2 discusses numerous proposals of functional projections appearing
within the DP. Sections 2.1 to 2.3 present an Agreement Phrase (AgrP), a Number
Phrase (NP) and a Quantifier Phrase (QP). Section 2.4 is concerned with the order of
adjectives within a nominal phrase from Cinque’s (1994) and Scott’s (2002)
perspective. Section 2.5 introduces the proposal of nP (a little n). In section 2.6 a
Demonstrative Phrase (DemP) and a Possessive Phrase (PossP) are discussed. Finally,
section 2.6 provides a discussion of the hierarchy of elements appearing within a DP.
30
2.1 AgrP - Agreement Phrase
The issue of agreement between various elements appearing within a DP was
raised by Abney (1987) and introduced as one of the cross-linguistic facts proving the
similarity of verbal and nominal phrases. Agreement is understood to be a feature
carried by the head of the phrase - D (cf. Chapter 1 (13)). It is manifested by proper
forms of nouns and neighbouring elements showing the same number, person or case.
On the basis of Hungarian data, Szabolcsi (1994) postulates the existence of Agreement
as a whole projection intervening between NP and DP. The data demonstrating this
problem are shown in (1).
(1) a. az en kalap-om
the I hat-1
st
sing.
‘my hat’
b. a te kalap-od
the you hat- 2
nd
sing.
‘your hat’
c. a Peter kalap-ja
the Peter- NOM hat-3
rd
sing.
‘Peter’s hat’
As can be seen in (1), Hungarian possessors are marked with nominative case
and show agreement with the noun that follows them. This structure is an exact
reflection of the relation between a subject and a verb within a sentence. What is more,
Hungarian possessors may also occupy frontal position within the nominal phrase,
preceding the article and the noun, as in (2b).
(2) a. a Mari kalap-ja
the Mari- NOM hat-3
rd
sing.
‘Mary’s hat’
31
b. Mari-nak a kalap-ja
Mari- DAT the hat- 3
rd
sing.
‘Mary’s hat’
Szabolcsi (1994) claims that (2b) is derived from (2a). The possessor Mari
occupying the position of [Spec; AgrP] moves leftwards to the [Spec; DP] where it is
assigned the dative case. The structure introduced by Szabolcsi is as follows (cf. (1a-c)
and (2a-b)):
(3) DP
Spec
D’
D
AgrP
Spec Agr’
Agr
NP
az
en
-om
kalap
a
te
-od
kalap
a
Peter -ja
kalap
a
Mari -ja
kalap
Mari- nak
i
a
t
i
-ja
kalap
Another piece of evidence in favour of the AgrP is based on the comparative
analysis of the position of particular adjectives in Romance and Germanic languages
and parametrised N-to-Agr movement postulated by Cinque (1994). By comparing
English and Italian data, it can be seen that some adjectives appearing prenominally in
English follow the noun in Italian (cf. (4 a-b)).
(4) a. the beautifu big red ball
[English]
b. la bella grande palla rossa
[Italian]
the beautiful big ball red
(Cinque (1994;93))
32
The classical GB analysis of Adjective Phrases assumes that they are attached to
the nominal phrase by adjunction. Due to the fact that they are neither complements nor
specifiers of the Noun Phrase they can recursively occur in the position intervening
between nouns and determiners and therefore create the structure presented in (5)
below.
(5) N’’
Spec N’
AP N’
AP
N’
AP
N’
N
(Radford (1988: 201))
However, the structure in (5) does not account for the data in (4) – it is actually
just the opposite: it creates a conceptually unsatisfactory result of allowing left-
adjunction in Germanic languages but right-adjunction in Romance. The structural
difference between the data in (4a-b) can be explained in two ways: either by claiming
that the final adjective in Romance languages is lowered into the position below the
noun, or proposing the leftward movement of a noun from the N position into some
empty head position intervening between the two APs.
Cinque (1994) supports the thesis of leftward noun movement. The piece of
evidence he produces is based on similar verb movement present in both language
33
groups (i.e. the obligatory raising of a finite V). As a result, the following structure is
postulated:
(6) DP
Spec D’
D AgrP
Spec Agr’
AP
Agr AgrP
Spec Agr’
AP
Agr AgrP
Spec Agr’
AP
Agr NP
N’
N
a.
the beautiful
big red ball
b.
la bella
grande palla
i
rossa
t
i
As can be seen in (6), Cinque rejects the classical GB interpretation of adjectives
treated as adjuncts of the NP, adjoined to the N’ and expanding it into another N’, and
places them in the position of [Spec;AgrP]. This leaves us with empty Agr head
positions within each AgrP, constituting possible landing sites for head-to-head
movement. At the same time, the conceptually unsatisfactory difference between left-
34
and right-adjunction ceases to exist. Therefore, the noun – adjective order within a DP
may differ across languages.
2.2 NumP- Number Phrase
On the basis of data from Celtic and Semitic languages the notion of Number
Phrase has been developed (Ritter (1988, 1991), Duffield (1995), Mohammad (1988),
Lyons (1997), among others). The elements of nominal phrases in these languages show
strong agreement with respect to number and gender. Therefore, although all the lexical
elements originate within the NP, they are moved higher to be assigned case (the head
noun) or to gain the proper number and gender (modifying elements – possessors)
(Ritter (1991)).
The structure proposed by Duffield (1995), after Ritter (1991) and others, with
proper examples is presented in (7) below:
35
(7) DP
Spec D’
D AgrP
Spec Agr’
Agr NumP
Spec Num’
Num NP
AP NP
Spec
N
a. sieq
i
Willy
j
t
i
t
i
l-leminija t
j
t
i
b. guth
i
t
i
t
i
aidir an tsagairt t
i
c. an leabhar
i
nua
t
i
a. sieq Willy l-leminija
[Hebrew]
foot-fem. sing. Willy the-right-fem. sing.
‘Willy’s right foot’
b. guth aidir an tsagairt
[Irish]
voice strong the priest-GEN
‘the priest’s powerful voice’
c. an leabhar nua
[Irish]
the book new
‘the new book’ (Duffield (1995: 309)
Assuming that the core position of all elements within a phrase is universal for
all languages, the same structure should appear in Celtic and in Semitic languages.
36
Therefore, the basic position of both the modifying adjective phrase and the possessor is
on the left-hand side of the Noun. The possessor, later on, moves to its target site from
the A’-position in [Spec;NP] to the [Spec;AgrP]. The functional projection of Number
caries the features of number and gender, and provides the landing site for the Noun.
The head noun is said to move from the N position to the functional position of Num
which accounts for the leftward position of the head noun in relation to the possessor
and modifying adjective phrases. In Irish, the Noun undergoes head-to-head movement
either to Num or to D if the latter is not occupied by some other element (cf. (7b) and
(7c)).
The NumP is one of the first functional projections claimed to appear between a
DP and an NP. However, there is no proof for its existence in Germanic and Slavic
languages. Therefore it will not be mentioned in Chapter 3, devoted to the structure of
Polish nominals.
2.3. QP - Quantifier Phrase
Apart from articles, possessors and demonstratives, another important group of
modifiers are quantifiers (e.g. some, many, all, (a) little, (a) few etc.). Although they are
in the complementary distribution with articles, they are recognized as a different class
requiring their own projection within the nominal phrase – a Quantifier Phrase.
However, the position of the Quantifier Phrase is not explicit. Following Giusti (1991,
1997), we must consider the existence of three different groups of quantifiers appearing
in different positions: quantifiers which must precede an article, as in (8), quantifiers
37
that may follow an article, as in (9), and quantifiers that do not co-occur with articles, as
in (10):
(8) a. tutti *(i) ragazzi
‘all the children’
b. *i tutti ragazzi
c. li ho visti tutti
‘I saw them all’
(9) a. molti Ø *i ragazzi
‘many boys’
b. i molti ragazzi
‘the many boys’
c. ne ho visti molti/ *ne ho visti i molti
‘I saw many of them’
(10) a. alcuni/ *i ragazzi
‘some boys’
b. ne ho visti alcuni .
‘I saw some of them’
(Giusti (1997: 114))
The quantifiers like molti ‘many’ behave like adjectives. They follow the article
and, when placed in the phrase initial position, they cause the expression to become
ungrammatical (cf. (9a) and (9b)). At the same time, they show agreement with regard
to umber and gender with the head noun. Therefore, it is possible to claim that, in fact,
they belong to the same lexical class as common adjectives. Consequently, just as
adjectives, they appear in a DP internal position of the high [Spec; AgrP], as shown in
(11) below.
38
(11) DP
D
AgrP
Spec Agr’
Agr
NP
Spec N’
AP
N
i due ragazzi simpatici t
i
the
two boys nice
(Giusti (1997: 115))
A piece of evidence supporting this theory is to be found in Romanian
encliticised definite article (Giusti (1991)). In Romanian, the definite article
encliticcises on the leftmost element of the nominal phrase: a noun or an adjective
moved into the D position. The same rule applies in the case of quantifiers and,
therefore, it is possible to claim that they do function as adjectives. As shown in (12) the
quantifier ambi ‘both,’ as well as the adjective frumosi ‘nice,' carries the encliticcsed
article.
(12) a. ambii baieti
both-the children
b. frumosii baieti
nice-the children
(Giusti (1994: 120))
39
However, according to Giusti (1991, 1994, 1997) not all quantifiers have the
same properties. The quantifiers as tutti 'all’ display selectional properties over the DP
they are followed by. They require the nominal phrase to be definite, therefore they are
followed by the article + noun construction as has been shown in (8a-b). The
explanation for this phenomenon proposed by Giusti (1991) is as follows: quantifiers
that are followed by articles are in fact external to DP and create their own projection
above the whole DP as shown in (13) below (cf. (8a)):
(13) QP
Spec Q’
Q DP
tutti
i ragazzi
all
the boys
(Giusti (1997. 114))
This analysis is repeated by Giusti and Leko (1995) in the context of pronominal
DPs modified by the quantifier tutti ‘all’ in Italian and its equivalents in French and
English. Comparing the data in (14a-c), with typical constructions of tutti + nominal
DP, as, for instance, in (8) and (13), they propose the structure shown in (15).
(14) a. voi/ noi tutti
[Italian]
b. nous/ vous tous
[French]
c. you/ we all
[English]
40
(15) QP
Spec Q’
Q DP
voi/noi
i
tutti
t
i
vous/nous
i
tous
t
i
you/we
i
all
t
i
According to Giusti and Leko (1995), pronouns originate within the DP and are
moved upwards to the [Spec; QP] position, as opposed to typical nominal DPs shown in
(13), which stay in the lower parts of the phrase. This claim, however, is highly
questionable. There seems to be no reason for the pronoun rising (this is not
syntactically motivated). What is more, Polish data discussed by Rutkowski (2002c)
constitute a clear set of counterarguments. The Polish equivalent of the quantifier tutti-
wszyscy, which behaves exactly like regular adjectives, shows strong agreement in
terms of case, number and gender with the head noun, as well as with the pronoun (cf.
(16)).
(16)
a. [wszyscy lingwiści] czytali mój artykuł
all linguists read my article
‘all linguists read my article’
b. [wy wszyscy] czytaliście mój artykuł
you all
read
my article
‘you all read my article’
c. *[wszyscy wy] czytaliście mój artykuł
all
you read
my article
(Rutkowski (2002c:163))
41
On the basis of data in (16), Rutkowski (2001, 2002a, 2002c) claims that both
the quantifier and pronoun are DP internal. The quantifier wszyscy is placed in the head
Q position and takes a complement, i.e. NP. The pronoun originates within the NP and
it is moved to the D position as a result of the N-to-D raising of pronouns. This leads to
the uniformity of the basic structure of Quantifier Phrase and neutralises the artificial
division of quantifiers. Rutkowski’s proposal is represented in the P-maker below.
(17) DP
Spec D’
D
QP
Spec
Q’
Q NP
GEN (Q)
wy-Gen
i
wszyscy
t
i
(Rutkowski (2007b:88))
However, the structure given by Rutkowski (2007b) is quite problematic.
According to the Head Movement Constraint, the element moved passes through each
head position intervening between the original and target positions. Here, the pronoun
wy skips an intervening Q, which is already occupied by wszyscy.
42
2.4 The order of adjectives
According to Abney (1987) (cf. Chapter 1, 1.3), adjectives constitute two separate
groups: pre-nominal adjectives, which form their own functional projection appearing in
the position intervening between a DP and an NP, and post-nominal adjectives, which
appear within Degree Phrases bellow the NP. What is more, adjectives are said to be
‘defective’ Nouns and fulfil similar functions within a DP as Auxiliaries within a CP.
However, there are some inconsistencies in Abney’s analysis of adjectives and
other components of the DP Hypothesis. According to Abney, Auxiliaries and
Determiners, being functional elements, are members of a closed class. They do not
contribute significantly to the meaning of the clause and are inseparable from the lexical
element they introduce. Adjectives, though claimed to be functional elements too, do
not match this description – they are members of an open lexical class, they can be
separated from the noun, and they do contribute to the meaning. At the same time, the
existence of post-nominal adjectives (the trigger for Abney’s interpretation) constitutes
the basis for Cinque’s (1994) analysis of Agreement Phrase (cf. Chapter 2, 2.1), which
postulates that APs occurring within a DP occupy the position of [Spec;AgrP] (cf. (6)).
Another query that stays unsolved under Abney’s analysis is the order of
Adjectives. In most languages elements modifying nouns have a strict and highly
restricted order of appearance. Each adjective appearing within a DP must be placed in
a proper position according to the semantic group it belongs to. According to the
research conducted by Pereltsvaig (2007), only 11.5% of native speakers of Russian do
not follow the universal order of adjectives. In this case Cinque’s (1994) analysis of
APs seems to be more justified. According to him, Adjective Phrases placed within
functional projections undergo selection under the conditions placed by the functional
43
head. Therefore, it is claimed that each Agreement Phrase hosting an AP within it
carries one of the attributive features, the order of which is as follows:
(18) possessor> cardinal> ordinal> quality> size> shape> colour> nationality
(Cinque (1994: 96))
The model presented by Cinque has undergone numerous modifications and
reshapings. New projections have been postulated and the analysis became more
detailed and specific. Scott’s (2002) analysis constitutes a good example of such
modification. According to Scott (2002), the number of AP-related functional
projections within a DP in much bigger than the eight introduced by Cinque (1994). The
universal hierarchy of DP elements proposed by him is as follows:
(19) Det> ordinal number> cardinal number> subjective comment> evidential>
size> length> height> speed> depth> width> weight> temperature> wetness>
age> shape> colour> nationality/origin> material> compound element> NP
(Scott (2002;114))
The application of the model is presented in (20) below.
44
(20) DP
D
D’
AdvP Subj. CommentP
AP
Subj. CommentP’
e
SizeP
e LengthP
AP LengthP’
(Scott (2002:106))
e ColourP
AP Colour P’
e
NP
What is more, Scott (2002) introduces the notion of Focus Phrase appearing
within the DP as an instance of another functional projection – the landing site for
elements undergoing preposing, i.e. the movement of the emphasised element towards
the left side of the phrase. The emphatic use of preposing in English is not uncommon.
The process can be applied even for more than one constituent. The emphasised
elements are moved to the [Spec;FocP] position, appearing below the DP, as shown in
(21).
(21) a. It’s [
DP
the green
i
big t
i
chair] that I want.
b. It’s [
DP
the old
j
green
i
big t
j
t
i
chair] that I want.
c. It’s [
DP
the nice green
i
big t
i
chair] that I want.
d. It’s [
DP
the nice green
i
old
j
big t
j
t
i
chair] that I want.
e.
[
DP
Carol’s horrible
i
six t
i
children] made life miserable for her second husband.
(Scott (2002: 113))
really
that
cool
long
red
dress
45
f.
DP
D’
D FocP
AP
FocP’
e
SizeP
AP ColourP
AP ColourP’
e
NP
All the proposals made by both Cinque (1994) and Scott (2002) are based
on the assumption that the order of adjectives within a nominal expression is
syntactically motivated and the influence of the speaker’s interpretation ends where the
preposing starts (Rutkowski (2007b)). Therefore, it is possible to assume that both
structures are universal. However, a more complex structure introduced by Scott (2002)
precisely exhausts the subject.
2.5 Little n - the nominal shells
One of the most awkward syntactic questions concerns the structure of constructions
with a ditransitive verb. According to the basic GB-theory assumptions, there could be
only one complement within a phrase and, due to this fact, the idea of the indirect object
being an additional complement is unacceptable. The analysis developed by Larson
(1988) and updated by Chomsky (1995a) casts light on this case. The analysis is as
the
green
i
big
t
i
chair
46
follows: a verbal phrase consists of two verbal projections – shells; the lower shell is the
projection of a lexical verb, whereas the higher one is the projection of a light verb - v,
which is given a null spell-out and whose meaning is closely connected with the
meaning of its complement. At the beginning, the lexical verb is merged between the
two objects, then it is adjoined to the light verb – v, which is strongly affixal in nature
and triggers the Move operation. An example structure is given in (22) below.
(22) a. Mary gave a book to John.
b. vP
Mary v’
v
0
VP
gave v
0
[
DP
a book] V’
V [
PP
to John]
gave
(Hornstein et al. (2005: 99))
The structure in (22) remains in agreement with The Uniformity of Theta
Assignment Hypothesis (UTAH) (Baker (1988, 1997)), which requires linking specific
theta-roles to particular positions in initial syntactic structure. And therefore the Theme
theta-role must be assigned to a book in the object position, the Goal theta-role to John,
and the Agent role must be assigned to Mary in the subject position.
Assuming that the structure of nominal expressions is similar or even identical
with the structure of verbal expressions, the existence of little n within the DP has been
proposed (cf.Valois (1996), Bhattacharya (1998), and many others). The little n selects
47
an NP and introduces an Agent. The surface order, again, appears to be the result of
Move operation (Adger (2003)). An example structure is presented below:
(23) a. Richard’s gift of the helicopter to the hospital
b. DP
Richard’s D’
D nP
Richard
n’
n
0
NP
gift
n
0
of the helicopter N’
gift to the hospital
(Adger (2003: 268))
The motivation for the existence of the little n is the case checking of the
nominal elements within the DP. D checks the Genitive case of the Agent and having a
strong [gen] feature causes the movement of the Agent from the [Spec;nP] position in
order to satisfy the locality requirement. The little n carries the weak [of] feature and,
due to this, it checks the case of the of-Phrase but does not cause movement (Adger
(2003)).
A more recent interpretation of this structure is presented by Radford (2004).
According to him, a lexical noun gift merges with its internal arguments: a Goal to the
hospital and a Theme of the helicopter. Then the NP merges with a little n, whose
specifier corresponds to the Agent phrase Richard. The little n is strongly affixal in
nature and therefore triggers the movement of the Noun. The whole nP merges with a
48
DP headed by a null Determiner. The null Determiner is able to assign the Genitive
case to the nominal Richard. The null D carries the [EPP] feature requiring it to be
extended into a DP projection with a proper specifier. As a result it triggers the
movement of the Richard to the [Spec; DP] position.
2.6 DemP – Demonstrative Phrase and PossP - Possessive Phrase
According to Abney (1987), articles, demonstratives and possessives occupy the same
syntactic position, i.e. a D position. This assumption is confirmed by the fact that those
elements in English are in complementary distribution. However, it is inconsistent with
the data taken from other Germanic, Romance and Slavic languages.
(24)
a. ta moja książka
[Polish]
this my book
‘this book of mine’
b. diese unserve wunderbaren Bücher
[German]
these our wonderful books
‘these wonderful books of ours’
(Rutkowski (2007b: 257-258))
As shown in (24) above, in some languages both possessive and demonstrative
pronouns can appear within one nominal phrase. Taking into consideration the data in
(24) it is no longer possible to claim that possessives and demonstratives occupy the
same position within the syntactic structure. What is more, they show agreement with
the Noun they modify, therefore, they are similar in syntactic behaviour rather to lexical
not to functional elements (Zlatić (1997)). In traditional perspective, Agreement is said
to involve a c-command relation between a modifier and an element modified, i.e. they
49
must fill a specifier and a head positions. To account for the presence of overt
agreement in the data in (24), it is possible to claim that both pronominal elements
occupy [Spec; XP] position. Due to the fact that a demonstrative pronoun usually
appears phrase-initially, Lecko (1999) suggests that it occupies [Spec, DP] position.
Then, a possessive pronoun must be placed in different Spec position. According to
Veselovská (1995), it appears within a Possessive Phrase, placed closely below a DP
projection. The structure steaming from the analysis presented above is shown in (25):
(25)
(Rutkowski (2007b:258))
According to Giusti (1997), the structure given in (25) above illustrates only the
final word order, which is a result of movements appearing during the derivation. This
is confirmed on the basis of data taken from Spanish presented in (26) below:
POSSESSIVE
PRONOUN
DEMONSTRATIVE
PRONOUN
NOUN
50
(26) a. este
libro
this- masc. sing book
‘this book’
b. el libro este
the book this-masc. sing.
‘this book’
c. *el este libro
the this-masc.sing. book
‘this book’
d. *este el libro
this-masc. sing. the book
‘this book’
(Rutkowski (2007b: 259-261))
As shown in (26), the demonstrative pronoun este may precede, as well as,
follow the noun. Giusti (1997) claims that a Demonstrative- Noun order presented in
(26a) is a result of a movent of the Noun. The overt agreement between the Noun and
the modifier may apply only if they are in a c-command relation, therefore it is not
possible to claim that a demonstrative originates lower in the structure than a Noun. As
far as the position of the Demonstrative is concerned, it can be neither a [Spec; DP] nor
a D position. The D position is already occupied by a definite article el (cf. (26 b-d)),
whilst the construction with a Demonstrative in [Spec; DP] position is ungrammatical
(cf. (26d)). Therefore, it is possible to claim that a demonstrative pronoun occupies a
specifier position within a Demonstrative Phrase (DemP) - a functional projection
appearing between a DP and an NP. From there it may be moved upward to [Spec; DP]
in order to satisfy the requirements connected with D
0
(Rutkowski (2007b)).
On the basis of the analysis presented above the initial position of possessive
pronouns may be established. In Spanish both demonstrative and possessive pronouns
may appear within one nominal phrase as shown in (27) below:
51
(27) el cuadro
i
redondo este suyo t
i
the picture round this his
‘this found picture of his’
(Rutkowski ( 2007b: 262))
According to Giusti (2002), the final syntax of el cuadro redondo este syuo is a
result of a movement of the Noun cuadro. The rest of the elements stay in their initial
positions. Therefore the possessive pronoun is claimed to appear within a projection
situated closely above the NP but lower than a DemP. Grohmann and Panagiotidis
(2004) suggest that [Spec; nP] should be accepted as the initial position of possessive
pronouns.
2.7 The hierarchy of functional elements within the DP
The issue closing this chapter pertains to the order of functional elements within the DP.
The result of my analysis will be the structure of nominal phrase which I will adopt in
this thesis
As has been shown in section 2.5, gift of the helicopter to the hospital is an nP.
Analysing examples given in (28) below, it is possible to establish the position of the nP
within the structure of DP:
(28) a. Richard’s [
nP
gift of the helicopter to the hospital]
(Adger (2003: 268))
b. my [
nP
gift of the helicopter to the hospital]
c. my generous [
nP
gift of the helicopter to the hospital]
d. Richard’s generous [
nP
gift of the helicopter to the hospital]
e. some generous [
nP
gift of the helicopter to the hospital]
f. *Richard’s [
nP
gift generous of the helicopter to the hospital]
g. *Richard’s [
nP
gift of the helicopter generous to the hospital]
h. *Richard’s [
nP
gift of the helicopter to the hospital] generous
i. *[
nP
gift of the helicopter to the hospital] some generous
52
As can be seen in (28 a-i), the little n stays lowest within the structure of the DP.
It is preceded by all the other elements, i.e. determiners, possessives, adjectives and
quantifiers. What is more, other functional elements of the DP intervening within the nP
cause the ungrammaticality of the phrase (cf. (28g-h)). On the basis of (28c-d), it may
be concluded that elements appearing under D, Possessives and Quantifiers, precede
APs. Therefore, bearing in mind the stipulations made in the previous sections of this
chapter, a claim could be made that the hierarchy of functional elements is as follows:
(29) DP
my D’
D PossP
my Poss’
Poss QP
Spec Q’
Q AgrP
generous Agr’
Agr nP
Spec n’
n
0
NP
gift
n
0
of the helicopter N’
gift to the hospital
However, there is still one functional projection already discussed but not included
within the structure above – i.e. the Number Phrase. According to Megerdoomian
53
(2008), the position of NumP is between the two nominal shells: the nP and the NP.
Following Travis (1992), Megerdoomian claims that Num carries the information about
the cardinality of the nominal phrase, and when projected, it gives the +SAQ (specified
quantity) interpretation to the noun phrase. This is necessary because this is the way in
which nominals, all marked as mass within the Lexicon, gain the count interpretation
(Megerdoomian (2008: 88) after Borer (2001)).
On balance, the structure of DP that I will adopt for the subsequent part of my
analysis of the nominal constructions is the structure consisting of all the projections
mentioned in this chapter and arranged in the following order of appearance:
(30)
DP> PossP> QP> AgrP
1
>…> AgrP
n
> nP> NumP> NP
I assume that the number of AgrPs appearing within the DP is not limited and that it
depends on the actual need, therefore in (30) AgrPs are provided with index numbers.
The index n expresses the theoretical lack of limit on the number of AgrPs within the
DP. The P-maker illustrating the structure is presented in (31) below:
54
(31)DP
D’
D PossP
Poss’
Poss QP
Spec Q’
Q AgrP
Spec Agr’
Agr nP
Spec n’
n
0
NumP
Spec Num’
Num NP
The Focus Phrase discussed in section 2.4 (cf. (21 f)) is not included within the
structure presented in (31). This is motivated by the fact that the presence of this
projection is necessary only in case of emphatic preposing which I will not discuss. The
lack of FocP does not disturb the order of projections, and it will not influence the
analysis that follows.
55
Conclusion
In Chapter 2, I have presented the structure of the DP has been presented, following the
recent analyses available in the literature. One by one, the functional projections
appearing within the nominal phrases: Possessor Phrase, Quantifier Phrase, Agreement
Phrases hosting Adjectives, little n and Number Phrase have been overviewed. Their
place within the nominal structure has been discussed and the reasons for postulating
the existence of each of them have been highlighted.
The Possessor Phrase is the first projection appearing bellow the DP, it hosts the
possessors. The PossP cannot appear in the same position as Saxon genitives - this is a
restriction steming from the UTAH. The second in the order of appearance is the
projection of Quantifiers. According to the theory of the Genitive of Quantification, the
QP is placed within the DP, even though it used to be claimed to be nominal-external.
Following the QP are the Agreement Phrases hosting Adjectives, whose order is
restricted and must follow the universal hierarchy. The number of possible AgrPs within
the DP is not restricted and depends on the need.
Below the AgrP complex, there appears the double layer of nominal shells: nP
and NP. The existence of nP has been proclaimed on the basis of the following three
assumptions:
4. the structure of nominal phrases should be as close to the structure of Verbal
phrases as possible.
5. the requirements of case checking within the nominal expression (especially
the locality condition not satisfied if Agent is claimed to Merge straight in
[Spec;DP] position)
56
6. the UTAH - the requirement linking specific theta-roles to particular
positions in initial syntactic structure.
The lowest projection within the DP is the NP - the projection of a lexical head -
a Noun, which can take complements, as has been assumed from the very beginning of
the research into the structure of nominal phrases.
57
Chapter 3
The DP in Polish
Introduction
Polish is a member of the group of languages which demonstrate no overt instantiation
of the functional element D. Therefore, it is not unexpectable to come across an analysis
of nominal phrases in Polish which assumes that there is no DP projection in this
language. However, the case of Polish is not an isolated one. The same feature may be
observed, among many others, in Chinese, Japanese and in other languages belonging to
the Slavic family. On the theoretical level of research pertaining to this topic, two major
ways of reasoning can be seen:
1. One presenting nominal phrases in languages mentioned strictly as NPs
without the DP layer, and therefore, explaining the syntactic difference
between languages with and without Determiners (Fukui (1986), Zlatić
(1997), Chierchia (1998), Willim (2000), Kim (2004), Bošković (2003,
2004, 2005, 2008) among others);
2. One adopting the idea of functional projection appearing above the NP
without an element, which could appear under D, at the same time being in
favour of universality of the syntactic structure (Corver (1992), Longobardi
(1994), Progovac (1998), Yadroff (1999), Migdalski (2000), Sio (2006),
Perltsvaig (2007), Rutkowski (2000, 2002a, 2002b, 2002c, 2007a, 2007b,
2009) among others).
In this chapter I will present both approaches to the DP, although, I am in
favour of the analysis positing the existence of DP in Polish. I will start by outlining the
58
arguments both for and against the NP interpretation of nominals (section 3.1). Later, I
will move towards the second interpretation, focusing mostly on the argumentation and
analysis as presented by Rutkowski (2007b) in his PhD dissertation. Finally, in section
I will concentrate on the structure, with the use of which Polish nominal phrases could
be described.
3.1 Is there a DP in Polish?
The existence of languages having in their lexicon no element that could function as an
article is not infrequently the major argument against proclaiming Abney’s DP
Hypothesis as universal (cf., for instance, Fukui (1986)). This observation makes
nominals be treated as they are understood under classical GB analysis – as NPs.
Consequently, the element D is still placed under the [Spec; NP] position and adjectives
are treated as adjuncts. The structure is shown in the P-maker in (1) below:
(1) NP
D
N’
AP N’
N
The same structure is applicable to Polish. It is supposed to explain phenomena
such as the Left Branch Extraction (LBE) or the impossibility of a nominal construction
59
with the double genitive (Bošković (2005, 2008)). Both phenomena are discussed in
detail in the following subsections of this chapter.
3.1.1 Left Branch Extraction (LBF)
The Left Branch Extraction is a key argument against applying the DP Hypothesis to
languages without a lexical instantiation of the functional Determiner. Bošković (2005,
2008) illustrates this on the basis of examples from Serbo-Croatian and Latin, shown
below:
(2) Serbo-Croatian:
a. Cijegi si vidio [t
i
oca]?
whose AUX-2
nd
sing. seen father
‘Whose father did you see?’
b. Tai je vidio [t
i
kola].
that AUX-3
rd
sing. seen car
‘That car, he saw.’
c. Lijepei je vidio [t
i
kuce].
beautiful AUX-3
rd
sing. seen houses
‘Beautiful houses, he saw.’
d. Kolikoi je zaradila [t
i
novca]?
how-much AUX-3
rd
sing. earned money
‘How much money did she earn?’
(3) Latin:
a. Cuiami amat Cicero [t
i
puellam]?
whose loves Cicero girl
‘Whose girl does Cicero love?’
b. Qualesi Cicero amat [t
i
puellas]?
what-kind-of Cicero loves girls
‘What kind of girls does Cicero love?’
(Bošković (2005: 2-3))
60
As can be seen in the examples above, pre-nominal modifiers in Serbo-Croatian
and in Latin can be extracted from within the nominal group. Their landing site is the
initial position on the left-hand side of the sentence (Bošković (2005)). The LBE is
characteristic for articleless languages only and, in languages like English, it is simply
ungrammatical (Uriagereka (1988), Bošković (2005, 2008)). According to Bošković
(2005, 2008), the difference between the two groups of languages lies in the fact that
languages with articles have a DP projection, whereas articleless languages have only
an NP projection - the traditional NP. What is more, they differ in the position of
Adjectives. In DP-languages, as suggested by Abney (1987) (cf. Chapter 1, section 1.3),
Adjectives are heads of a functional projection appearing between a DP and an NP,
therefore, they alone do not form a full constituent and cannot be extracted – as being a
full constituent is a condition for extraction. In non-DP-languages, on the other hand,
Adjectives are adjuncts, therefore they form constituents and are prone to extraction
(Bošković (2005)). The graphical representation of nominal phrases and the LBE in
both languages is shown in (4) and (5) below:
(4) LBE in DP-languages
(Rutkowski (2007b; 56))
61
(5) LBE in non-DP-languages:
(Rutkowski (2007b;56))
According to the Minimalist theory, it is possible to claim that in the case of the
LBE discontinuous or scattered spellout occurs (Fanselow and Ćavar (2002)).
According to Chomsky (1995a, 2000), each movement takes place in two stages:
Copying and Deletion (the copy theory of movement). Firstly, the element which
undergoes movement is copied and merged in the target position. Later, the original
copy is deleted, i.e. is given a null spellout. As Fanselow and Ćavar (2002) suggest, in
the case of the LBE, the null spellout can be applied only to the part of the constituent
undergoing movement. Then, not the whole original element is removed, but a part of
each copy undergoes deletion, as shown in the example below:
(6)
a. [Którą książkę] chcesz przeczytać [którą książkę]?
b. [Którą książkę] chcesz przeczytać [którą książkę]? (Rutkowski (2007b:58))
62
As can be seen in (6a) the movement of the wh-phrase którą książkę is the effect
of copying of the whole wh-phrase, merging it in the sentence-initial position and,
finally, deleting the entire lower copy. (6a) and (6b) do not differ in the application of
wh-movement, however, in the case of sentence in (6b) after copying and merging,
discontinuous spell-out takes place, i.e. the wh-phrase is deleted in the lower copy,
while the noun is given a null spell-out in the upper copy.
According to Rutkowski (2007b), Bošković’s (2005), analysis is questionable as
regards the most recent interpretation of Adjectives. As claimed by Cinque (1994), APs
do not constitute separate functional projections intervening between a DP and an NP
but, instead, they are placed in [Spec; AgrP] position (cf. Chapter 2, section 2.1). In this
analysis they form full constituents and, theoretically, are capable of undergoing
extraction. Therefore the LBE must be blocked not only when AP is not a constituent.
The graphical representation of this analysis is presented in (6) below. For the sake of
simplicity the AgrP is not included within the structure and AP is shown as occupying
[Spec;NP].
(6) Theoretical LBE in DP-languages
(Rutkowski (2007b:57))
63
The second condition on the LBE is also discussed by Bošković (2008).
Following Chomsky’s (2000) reasoning, he claims that a DP, just as a CP, is a phase.
Chomsky (2001) claims that any syntactic operation involves a local relation between a
probe and a goal. A phase is impenetrable in nature, i.e. it blocks the realtion between
an external probe and internal gole. Assuming that a DP is a phase, the LBE is allowed
only if the AP moves outside the DP through the [Spec;DP] position (Bošković (2008)).
This condition is also fulfilled under Rutkowski’s (2007b) analysis. Assuming that an
AP is in the [Spec; AgrP] position it can undergo movement to another Specifier
position: i.e. [Spec; DP]. In articleless languages (e.g. Polish) this position is empty,
therefore the movement is not blocked. On the contrary, in languages with articles, the
[Spec; DP] position is already occupied and movement cannot apply.
What is more, according to Linde-Usiekniewicz and Rutkowski (2007b), there
are two features of Polish nominal coordination that do not support Bošković’s (2005)
interpretation. NP-external adjectival modification of coordinated phrases and phrasal
coordination at various levels are possible only if we assume the DP analysis of Polish
nominals. Bošković (2005) claims that numerals, just like adjectives and other
modifiers, are NP-internal. This model gives no explanation for the construction
presented in (8) below:
(8)
dziewięciuset profesorów, doktorantów i studentów
nine-hundred professors PhD-students and MA-students
‘nine hundred professors, PhD-students and MA-students’
(Linde-Usiekniewicz and Rutowski (2007b:113))
64
The phrase in (8) allows one interpretation: ‘there were nine hundred people
altogether: professors, PhD-students and MA-students’ If consistent with Bošković’s
(2005) model, this phrase should have a completely different interpretation, i.e.: ‘there
were nine-hundred professors and some PhD-students and some MA-students’,
however, it cannot be taken into consideration as all the three nominals are assigned
genitive by the numeral. This fact suggests that the numeral must be NP-external
(Linde-Usiekniewicz and Rutkowski (2007a)).
What is more, Bošković’s (2005) analysis gives no explanation for the examples
of coordination at various levels given bellow:
(9)
a. te piec dobrych polskich policjantek i lingwistek
these five good Polish policewomen and linguists
‘these five good Polish policewomen and linguists.’
b. te piec dobrych polskich policjantek i niemieckich lingwistek
these five good Polish policewomen and German linguists
‘these five good Polish policewomen and German linguists.’
c. te piec dobrych polskich policjantek i wspaniałych niemieckich lingwistek
these five good Polish policewomen and excellent German linguists
‘these five good Polish policewomen and excellent German linguists.’
d.
te piec dobrych polskich policjantek i siedem wspaniałych niemieckich lingwistek
these five good Polish policewomen and seven excellent German linguists
‘these five good Polish policewomen and seven excellent German linguists.’
e. te piec dobrych polskich policjantek i tamte siedem wspaniałych
these five good Polish policewomen and those seven excellent
niemieckich lingwistek
German linguists
‘these five good Polish policewomen and those seven excellent German
linguists.’
(Linde-Usiekniewicz and Rutkowski (2007b;115))
According to Bošković (2005), these phrases are not phrasal constituents and,
therefore, it should not be possible for them to be coordinated. However, assuming the
65
DP interpretation of nominals, we obtain a number of phrasal levels, that allow
coordination. In this model, the following interpretation of examples in (9) is made:
(10) a.
[DP [NumP [AgrP-EVALUATION [_P-ORIGIN [ConjP]]]]] NP coordination
b. [DP [NumP [AgrP-EVALUATION [ConjP]]]] AgrP-ORIGIN coordination
c.[DP [NumP [ConjP]]] AgrP-EVALUATION coordination
d. [DP [ConjP]] NumP coordination
e. [ConjP] DP coordination
(Linde-Usiekniewicz and Rutkowski (2007b:115))
3.1.2 Double genitive constructions
According to Willim (2000), there are two positions within the DP structure of nominals
in which genitive can be assigned, i.e. the complement of NP and Specifier of DP. In
Polish, however, the nominal construction with two genitives is ungrammatical, as
shown below:
(11) *odkrycie Ameryki Kolumba
discovery America-GEN Columbus-GEN
‘the discovery of America by Columbus’
(Rutkowski (2007b:66))
Willim (2000) claims that this is a strong argument against analyzing articleless
languages as DP-languages. This lack of a DP layer makes a double genitive
construction impossible. At the same time similar examples taken from Russian, also an
articleless language, are perfectly grammatical (Engelhardt and Trugman (1998))
(12)
analiz poèmy Puškina literaturoveda
analysis (of) poem Puskin-GEN literary scholar-GEN
‘the analysis of Pushkin’s poem by literary scholar’
(Rutkowski (2007b:67) after Engelhardt and Trugman (1998))
66
As can be seen in (12), Russian allows double genitive constructions, therefore,
according to Engelhardt and Trugman (1998), this is a strong argument for introducing
the DP analysis. Aspiring to forming a universal model of language structure induces us
to apply the same theory to Polish and other articleless languages. Therefore, we may
accept the analysis of Longobardi (2001), who claims that genitive case assignment is
not strictly connected to the D position, but it is generated lower within the functional
layer between a DP and an NP. This allows us to assume that the existence of double
genitive construction is subject to parametric restrictions, various for different
languages.
3.1.3 The Lack of N-to-D movement
According to Longobardi (1994), N-to-D movement is one of the arguments for
postulating the existence of the DP layer in English and the explanation of the Italian
word order within nominal phrases. Italian nominals show a reversed order of
Adjectives toward the Noun in the case of referential expressions like proper names.
(13) a. *E’ venuto vecchio Cameresi.
Come-pasti-3
rd
sing older Cameresi
‘Came older Cameresi’
b. E’venuto Cameresi vecchio
Come-pasti-3
rd
sing Cameresi older
‘Came older Cameresi’
c. E’venuto il Cameresi vecchio
Come-pasti-3
rd
the sing Cameresi older
‘Came the older Cameresi’
(Longobardi (1994:18))
As can be seen from the examples above, Italian recquires Noun-Adjective order in
referential constructions with proper names. The explanation given by Longobardi
67
(1994) assumes that the functional position D cannot stay unfilled when the nominal
phrase has a definite reference. The requirement is fulfilled by the N-to-D movement of
the proper name, as illustrated in (14) below:
(14)
(Rutkowski (2007b;31))
A similar movement appears in other languages, for instance, in English – the
case of someone, anyone, etc. (Abney (1987)) (cf . Chapter 1, example (22) and its
explanation), or in Romanian definite nominal phrases with articles cliticized on nouns
as shown below (Rutkowski (2007b) after Dobrovie-Sorin (1987) and Grosu (1988)).
(15) băiat
i
-ul frumos t
i
boy
i
-art-def nice t
i
‘the nice boy’
According to Willim (2000) the lack of overt N-to-D movement in the Polish
language is another argument against applying the DP Hypothesis to Polish nominals.
The construction as Carmenesi stary - ‘Carmenesi old’ is ungrammatical, accepted only
when used in poetry, which does not show the typical rules of grammar.
68
However, as has already been mentioned in the previous chapter (cf. Chapter 2,
section 2.4) N-to-D movement applies not only to Nouns but also to Pronouns and
Quantifiers. As has been shown in examples (16) and (17), taken from Rutkowski
(2002c), movement to the D position in Polish does exist. Similar observations were
made by Progovac (1998) with respect to another articleless language, Serbo-Croatian.
(16) a. I samu Mariju to nervira.
and alone Marija this irritate.
‘This irritates even Mary’
b. I nju, mene samu to nervira.
and Her,me alone this irritates
‘This irritates even her’
(Progovac (1998:83-84))
In Serbo-Croatian pronouns, being similar to Nouns in their features, originate in
the same position as Nouns, i.e. N
0
. Later on, due to the referential difference, they are
moved to the D
0
position. The adjective, placed in the middle between a DP and an NP,
stays in one place. The movement of the pronoun can be explained only under the DP
analysis of nominals.
3.1.4 Other arguments against the DP analysis of Polish nominals
As has been shown in sections 3.1.1 to 3.1.3 of this chapter, initially irrefutable
arguments against the DP interpretation of nominal phrases in articleless languages do
not hold when contrasted with the language data. The crowning argument of the DP
opponents is the lack of articles in languages like Polish. However, this argument is also
to be invalidated.
69
According to Migdalski (2000), the case of the whole phrase is strictly
connected to the phrase referential aspect. Thus, genitive constructions represent the
indefinite reference, whilst accusative constructions – definite. In this respect, the dative
construction fulfils similar function as the quantifier trochę ‘a bit’ (Rutkowski (2007b)).
The data confirming this thesis are shown in (17) below.
(17) a. Zapakowałem mąki
pack-past-1
st
sing flour-DAT
‘I packed flour.’
b. Zapakowałem mąkę.
pack- past-1
st
sing flour- ACC
‘I packed the flour’
(Rutkowski (2007b:73))
Another argument against the existence of a DP layer in articleless languages is
mentioned by Willim (2000) - i.e. a similarity between demonstratives and adjectives,
that makes the former unable to fill the D
0
position. However, in the light of the newest
interpretation of the position of Demonstratives and Possessives (Brugè (2002), Giusti
(2002), Julien (2002), Roehers (2006), Rutkowski (2007b), among others) this
similarity provides support for the DP Hypothesis. In fact, elements belonging to both
groups, demonstratives and possessives, are derived within the lower parts of the
functional layer of nominal expressions and later they are moved leftwards, respectively
to the [Spec;DP] and [Spec;PossP] position (this movement and the structure will be
discussed in detail in section 3.2.3 of this chapter). The P-maker presenting the structure
is shown below (cf. Chapter 2, section 2.7, (29)):
70
(18)
(Rutkowski (2007b:265))
3.2 The internal structure of nominal phrases in Polish
As has been proved in the previous section of this chapter, the DP analysis of
nominal phrases in languages like Polish is highly motivated by language data. The lack
of articles, i.e. the overt instantiations of the functional D in a language, is not an
argument that refutes the need for postulating the existence of functional projections
heading nominals. In this section I will prove that postulating these projections in Polish
is syntactically adequate and necessary.
DEMONSTRATIVE
NOUN
POSSESIVE
71
At the end of Chapter 2 (cf. (29)) I have presented the structure, which I will
make the basis of the further analysis of Polish language data. I have accepted the
following functional projections:
1. Determiner Phrase – the landing site for Demonstratives and Pronouns, the
basic position of Determiners;
2. Possessive Phrase – the landing site for Possessives;
3. Quantifier Phrase – the basic position of Quantifiers;
4. Agreement Phrases – a series of functional phrases hosting Adjective
Phrases in the position of [Spec;AgrP];
5. n Phrase – the landing site for a Noun, and the basic position of Possesives.
Aiming toward the universality of grammar we must assume that the same
structure applies to other languages, also those articleless.
(19)
Już przyszło [
DP
tych [
PossP
waszych
i
[
QP
pięciu [
AgrP
zdolnych [
nP
t
i
[
NP
uczniów]]]]]].
Already come-past- 3
rd
pl this-pl-ACC your-pl-ACC five-ACC talented-pl-ACC student-pl-ACC.
‘Those five talented students of yours have already come.’
As can be seen in (19), Polish nominal phrases may appear with all the positions
filled. However, it is necessary to analyze Polish data that are similar to the data taken
from other languages, which were the basis for deriving the structure given in Chapter 2
in (29).
72
3.2.1. Noun – pronoun asymmetry. The position of personal pronouns.
The syntactic status of pronouns is rather ambiguous (Rutkowski (2007b)). According
to Progovac (1998), although pronouns appear in the DP-initial position within the
surface structure, in deep structure in fact they originate in the same positions as nouns.
This seems to be confirmed by the coordination of phrases with a Pronoun and with a
Noun, as shown in (20) below.
(20) a. To zrobili [oni wszyscy] i [tamten chłopak]
this do-past-3
rd
pl- masc. [they all] and [that boy].
‘All of them with that boy did it’
However, there are still data, presented by Rutkowski (2007b), that escape an
explanation.
(21)
a. Cały ty!
all you
‘That’s like you!’
b. Cały Cezary!
all Cezary
‘That’s like Cezary!’
c. *Ty cały!
you all
‘That’s like you!
(Rutkowski (2007b: 86))
As can be seen in (21) not in each case Pronouns must be moved to the D
position. According to Longobardi (2006) and Rutkowski (2007b), only Pronouns that
are the arguments of the predicate undergo N-to-D movement. In the case of examples
(21 a-c), due to the fact that the nominal expressions are not arguments, the movement
does not take place. At the same time the data constitute an argument for the N-to-D
movement analysis as they show the original position of Pronouns.
73
3.2.2. Adjectives
One of the most interesting points of Slavic syntax are the Adjectives. In comparison to
other languages e.g. English, they do not show strict hierarchy (cf. Chapter 2, exaple
(19)). According to Rutkowski (2007), it is the semantic context that determines the
grammaticality of the phrase.
(22) a. czarny amerykański samochód
black American car
b. amerykański czarny samochód
American black car
(Rutkowski (2007b:136))
According to Scott’s (2002) hierarchy, only the phrase in (22a) is expected to be
grammatical. However, Rutkowski (2007b), after Bosque and Picallo (1996), declares
both examples grammatical, giving them as examples of subspecification – the
cognitive hierarchization of information. The difference between the two phrases lies in
the semantic scope of both adjectives. Therefore, it changes with the context. The
meaning of the two phrases is given in (23) below:
(23) a. one of American cars, which is black
b. one of black cars, which is American
The more specific is the semantic information carried by an Adjective, the closer
to the modified Noun the Adjective appears. Because of this fact, there is no explicit
way to formulate a constant hierarchy of Adjective Phrases within Polish DPs.
Therefore, Rutkowski (2007b) proposes, after Julien (2002) and Pereltsvaig (2007), to
mark each functional phrase hosting an AP in the position of Specifier as αP (cf. AgrP
in Chapter 2, section 2.4) , as shown in (24):
74
(24) DP
D
αP
AP
α’
α
NP
N
0
(Rutkowski (2007b:130))
However, there is another phenomenon worth mentioning connected to Polish
adjectives: the existence of classifying or classificatory adjectives.
(25) a. gramatyka generatywna
generative grammar
b. piłka nożna
football
c. drzwi przeciwpożarowe
emergenct exit
(Rutkowski (2007b:144))
As can be seen in (25) not all adjectives appear prenominally in Polish. The
classifying Adjectives, which appear postnominally, are closely related to the Noun they
modify and they denote permanent, fundamental and distinctive feature of the Noun
(Rutkowski (2007b)). What is more, they all share other common properties:
1. They do not possess comparative and superlative: *garmatyka generatywniejsza
‘more generative grammar’, *gramatyka najgeneratywniejsza ‘the most
generative grammar’;
2. They cannot be coordinated: *gramatyka i nauka generatywna ‘generative
grammar and science’;
75
3. They do not appear in predicates: *Gramatyka jest generatywna. ‘The grammar
is generative’.
4. They are often generated from nouns: noga ’foot, leg’ - nożna ‘foot-operated’
Worth mentioning is also the fact, that some Adjectives functioning as classifying
adjectives may also appear as ordinary, descriptive adjectives. Then, they appear
prenominally (Rutkowski and Progovac (2005)).
(26) a. biedni ludzie [descriptive interpretation]
poor people
b. ludzie biedni
[classifying interpretation]
the poor
(27) a. obcy jezyk
[descriptive interpretation]
unknown language
b. język obcy
[classifying interpretation]
foreign language
(Rutkowski (2007b:147))
The data in (26) and (27) show adjectives in their both possible interpretations:
classifyng and descriptive. What is more, they suggest the interpretation of their
syntactic structure. Due to the fact that proclaiming the existence of two different
syntactic positions for one adjective would violate the economy condition postulated by
Chomsky (1995a), we may assume that the adjective has just one basic position, and the
movement of one element appears. According to the data presented by Rutkowski
(2007b), it is possible to claim only the movement of a Noun.
(28) a. straszny tygrys
‘fierce tiger’
b. straszny tygrys syberyjski
‘fierce Siberian tiger’
c. *tygrys straszny syberyjski
‘fierce Siberian tiger’
76
d. *tygrys syberyjski straszny
‘fierce Syberian tiger
(Rutkowski (2007b:162))
As can be seen in (28) adjectives in Polish appear mostly prenominally, only
classifying adjectives may appear post nominally. What is more, it is possible to use
only one classifying adjective at once. Therefore according to Rutkowski (2007b), the
classifying adjective appears within the NP, which explains its close relation to the
Noun. The NP is a complement of a Classification Phrase (ClassP) (Rutkowski and
Progovac (2005)), the head of which (Classification – Class
0
) functions as a landing site
for the moved noun (Rutkowski and Progovac (2005)). The whole structure, based on
the data from (28) is presented in (29) below.
(29)
(Rutkowski (2007b:163))
The only problem raised by Rutkowski and Progovac’s (2005) proposal is that
there is no cross-linguistic fact confirming the existence of the ClassP, which is
considered to appear only in Polish. Therefore, according to Rutkowski (2007b), it is
tygrys
i
syberyjski
77
possible to claim that a ClassP is in fact the same projection as an nP (cf. Chapter 2,
section 2.5), which according to recent analyses, is closest to the NP. Then the
movement of the Noun to the n position within the classifying construction corresponds
to the movement of a verb within double object constructions. The new structure is
given in (30).
(30)
(Rutkowski (2007b:178))
3.2.3. Possessive and demonstrative pronouns
Possessives and Demonstratives commonly appear in the initial positions within the
nominal phrase. Therefore, they are usually placed in the position within the two highest
projections: DP and PossP (cf. Chapter 2, structure (29). However, according to Gedeon
(2004), they must derive from the lower parts of the DP.
tygrys
i
syberyjski
78
Assuming that Possessive pronouns are the genitival realizations of personal
pronouns, Gedeon (2004) claims they must be generated within a DP complement of N,
in order to obtain the case. Later on they undergo extraction and are moved to the Poss
0
position. The structure is given below.
(31) a. joho brat
[Ukrainian]
his brother
b.
(Rutkowski (2007b:275))
According to Grohmann and Panagiotidis (2004), in Greek demonstrative and
possessive pronouns are generated just above the NP, due to this fact they may be freely
moved leftwards to PossP and DP. The data in (32) seem to confirm this claim.
79
(32) a. afta ta neo fenomena
this-pl the new phenonena
‘these new phenomena’
b. ta nea afta fenomena
the new this-pl phenomena
‘’these new phenomena’
(Rutkowski (2007b:262) after Grohmann and Panagiotidis (2004))
As can be observed in (32), Greek demonstratives may appear in two positions:
DP initially (derived after movement) and in strict neighborhood of the Noun (original)
(for the structure cf. (18)) According to Grohmann and Panagiotidis (2004), the
difference between these two positions is not only syntactic but also semantic: the first
one provides deictic reading whilst the second one corresponds to anaphoric.
3.3 The structure of Polish nominal phrases
Polish is a language allowing a reasonably free word order especially as far as
adjectives are concerned. However, it is still possible to distinguish the hierarchy of
main elements appearing within nominal phrases. To account for this fact we must
accept the DP analysis of nominals allowing the existence of functional layers. In the
previous sections of this chapter I presented the necessity of proclaiming the existence
of the Determiner Phrase together with other functional projections in Polish. The order
of which is as follows:
(33) DP > PossP > QP > αP > … > αP > DemP > nP > NP with classifying AP
The construction accounting for all most important language data is presented
below:
80
(34) a. ten nasz jeden wielki biały niedźwiedź polarny
this our one big white polar bear
b. DP
Spec D’
D PossP
Poss QP
Q
αP
AP
α’
α αP
AP α’
α DemP
Dem nP
n
NP
AP N’ GEN
N
DP
ten
i
nasz
j
jeden wielki
biały t
i
niedźwiedź
k
polarny t
k
t
j
81
As can be seen in (34) above, the surface structure of the noun phrase ten nasz
jeden wielki bialy niedźwiedź polarny is derived by means of movements. The Noun is
moved leftward from N
0
to the n
0
affixal in nature creating the NP – AP order
characteristic for classifying constructions. Before that, the Noun assigns Genitive case
to the DP my/nasz, which is later on moved to its target position in Poss
0
. The last
movement applies to the Demonstrative originating under Dem
0
and moved to the
phrase initial position in [Spec;DP]. The order of descriptive adjectives has been
established on the basis of subspecification, and in this case it is in accordance with
Scott’s (2002) hierarchy of adjectives. Polish lacks elements that could appear under D
0
therefore this position stays unfilled by any overt element.
However, there is one question left without answer. There is no reason given for
the movement of the possessive pronoun nasz and the Demonstrative ten. The existence
of different word order patterns in various languages is not a motivation sufficient for
proclaiming the existence of the movements mentioned above.
Conclusion
In this chapter I have focused on the internal structure of Polish nominals. I have shown
that the crowning arguments in favor of the NP analysis of nominal phrases in this
language are not adequate. The Left Branch Extraction (LBE) can be easily accounted
for by appealing to discontinuous spell-out. What is more, NP-external adjectival
modification of coordinated phrases and phrasal coordination at various levels discredit
82
the LBE as an argument against the DP analysis. Similarly, the ungrammaticality of
double genitive construction does not bear on the NP character of Polish nominal
phrases. Since they are grammatical in other articleless languages, double genitives are
claimed to be subject to parametric restrictions independent of the presence of the DP
layer within a nominal construction. What is more, the absence of articles in languages
like Polish appears to be motivated by the presence of overt morphological case, which,
according to Migdalski (2002), is able to carry the definiteness denotation. Finally, the
presence of the DP layer is confirmed by the existence of N-to-D movement in
articleless languages, which is manifested by the reversed order of Adjectives with
respect to pronouns, i.e. only with Pronouns descriptive adjectives appear post-
nominally.
As far as the very internal structure of the DP in Polish is concerned, the
structure does not strikingly stray from the universal structure of DPs presented in the
previous chapter. However there are two facts worth mentioning. First of all, in Polish
we may observe two separate kinds of Adjectives that appear in two different positions,
i.e. descriptive and classifying adjectives. Classifying adjectives are strictly connected
to the Noun they modify – they influence the semantic meaning of the nominal head of
the phrase. Therefore, they are claimed to have an NP-internal origin. On the contrary
descriptive adjectives appearing prenominally fill the position of [Spec;αP] and undergo
universal hierarchy dependencies, typical for this class. However, their order may
undergo changes under special interpretational circumstances.
What is more, the notion of movement of Demonstrative and Possessive
pronouns has been hinted at. Possessive pronouns are claimed to originate within the
DP complement of the Noun where they can be assigned case and afterwards they are
83
moved to their surface position in PossP. Similarly, Demonstrative Pronouns showing
the strict agreement with the Noun with respect to person, number and gender must
originate within the DemP appearing closer to the NP than their surface position,
namely [Spec; DP].
84
Summary and conclusions
This dissertation has examined the structure of nominal phrases in English and Polish. It
started with the presentation of the early GB analysis of nominals and continued with
Abney’s (1987) DP Hypothesis and more recent accounts of the DP structure. The main
aims have been:
to reveal the shortcomings of the early GB account of the nominal phrases,
to outline the main assumptions of the DP Hypothesis,
to examine the status of elements intervening between a DP and an NP,
to point out and examine the most important functional projections appearing
within the nominal structure,
to establish the order of the functional projections within a DP,
to analyse and evaluate the arguments against the DP analysis of Polish
nominals,
to examine the application of the DP analysis of nominal phrases for application
to Polish syntax,
to provide a structure capable of capturing all properties of Polish nominal
phrases.
The first part of Chapter 1 focused on the classical GB account of nominals. It
has been shown that although the NP analysis of nominals accounts for the Binary
85
Branching and Singlemotherhood Constraints, it fails to capture all properties of
nominal phrases. The main problems are summarised below:
- Both demonstratives and possessives are considered to be determiners, therefore
there is no explanation for the co-occurrence of possessives and demonstratives
or articles within one phrase.
- The similarity between nominal and verbal phrases is not covered.
- The word order of the elements intervening between an article and a Noun is not
given any justification. All the elements are treated as adjuncts.
- Determiners constitute an exception within lexical and functional elements of a
language as they do not project any further.
The subsequent aim was to present the basic assumptions of Abney’s DP
Hypothesis. It has been shown that a nominal phrase is headed by a functional element
D. The similarities between a clause and a nominal phrase have been demonstrated on
the basis of the existence of an internal Agreement, an introducing Complementizer
and a head-to-head movement appearing both in clausal and nominal constructions.
Furthermore, additional functional projections intervening between a DP and an NP
have been established. The elements traditionally recognised as adjuncts have been
placed within an Adjective Phrase and an Degree Phrase. The fixed word order of
modifiers within a DP has been accounted for on the basis of the specifier – head –
complement order of phrase structure.
86
The main goal of Chapter 2 was to present and examine the most important
functional projections appearing within a DP. The projections discussed in this
dissertation are as follows:
- Agreement Phrase – developed on the basis of Abney’s (1987) analysis of an
AP, a host to [Agr] feature and later an Adjective Phrase;
- Number Phrase – present in Celtic and Semitic languages, is not important for
the analysis of Polish nominals; this projection carries the features of number
and gender and constitutes the landing site for a Noun;
- Quantifier Phrase – a host to Quantifiers, similar to Agreement Phrase;
- Focus Phrase – connected with the order of adjectives, a landing site of an
element which undergoes preposing;
- n Phrase – a nominal shell, as an equivalent of v; the landing site for a Noun;
- Demonstrative Phrase – the initial position of Demonstratives, which are later
on moved to the Specifier position within a DP;
- Possessive Phrase – the landing site of possessive elements originating below
the Noun.
Subsequently, the order of adjectives within a noun phrase has been discussed.
Following Cinque’s (1994) and Scott’s (2002) analyses it has been shown that
adjectives must be placed in a proper position according to their semantic group.
The aim of the second part of Chapter 2 was to analyse the hierarchy of
functional projections within the DP structure. On the basis of examples it has been
established that the little n stays closest to the NP, with exception of Number Phrase in
Celtic and Semitic languages. Higher within the structure are placed Agreement
87
projections hosting adjectives and a Quantifier Phrase. Possessive Phrase is placed
directly below the DP.
The main aim of Chapter 3 was to examine the structure of Polish nominals. In
the first part of the chapter the analysis treating Polish nominal phrases as NPs has been
presented and evaluated. The starting point for this analysis were the differences
between languages with and without articles. However, it has been revealed that the
phenomena, such as, for instance: The Left Branch Extraction or double genitive
cinstructions, considered to function as crucial arguments against the DP interpretation
of Polish noun phrases are also accounted for under the DP analysis.
In the second part of Chapter 3 Rutkowski’s (2007b) DP analysis of Polish
nominal phrases has been presented and recognised as satisfactory. The main
assumptions of this analysis are listed below:
- Although, there is no overt instantiation of articles in the Polish language, Polish
nominals are headed by a functional element D.
- N-to-D movement applies only to Pronouns that are the arguments of the
predicate.
- The Presence of classifying adjectives constitutes an argument for claiming the
existence of nP within Polish noun phrases.
- The agreement between a noun and demonstrative or possessive elements
indicates that the latter originates lower within the structure than the DP
projection.
The final aim of Chapter 3 was to offer the structure of Polish DP. On the basis of
Rutkowski’s (2007b) analysis all the important functional projections and their order
88
have been established. The following phenomena have been taken into consideration:
movements of a Noun, a Demonstrative Pronoun and a Possessive Pronoun, the
existence of two different groups of adjectives. The final structure has been shown not
to stray from the universal structure of DPs.
To conclude, the structure of a DP appears to be as complicated as the structure of a
clause. Most of the research done focuses on a single aspect of the structure or a single
language, therefore, it is difficult to provide an exhaustive universal model of a DP
structure. At the same time the DP analysis has not been accepted as universal and
further works based on the NP approach toward nominals are continuously offered.
89
References
Abney, Stephen P.1987. The English noun phrase in its sentential aspect. Doctoral
dissertation, The Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
Adger, David. 2003. Core syntax. A Minimalist Approach. Oxford and New York:
Oxford University Press.
Baker, Mark C. 1988. Incorporation: A theory of grammatical function changing.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Baker, Mark C. 1997. Thematic Roles and Syntactic Structure. In Elements of
Grammar. Handbook of Generative Syntax ed. Liliane Haegeman, 73-137.
Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Bhattacharya, Tanmoy. 1998. DP-internal NP movement . In UCL working papers in
linguistics 10, eds. John Harris and Corinne Iten, 225-251. London: Department
of Linguistics and Phonetics, University College London.
Borer, Haigit. 2001. Plurals and Clasifiers. Ms., University of Southern California.
Borer, Haigit. 2005a. Structuring sense: In name only. Oxford and New York: Oxford
University Press.
Borer, Haigit. 2005b. Structuring sense: The normal course of events. Oxford, New
York: Oxford University Press.
Bošković, Željko. 2003. On left branch extraction . In Investigations into formal Slavic
linguistics: contributions of the Fourth European Conference on Formal
Description of Slavic Languages – FDSL IV held at Potsdam University,
90
November 28-30, 2001, eds. Peter Kosta, Joanna Błaszczak, Jens Frasek, Ljudmila
Geist and Marzena Żygis, 543-577. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.
Bošković, Željko. 2004. Topicalization, focalization, lexical insertion, and scrambling.
Linguistic Inquiry 35: 613-638.
Bošković, Željko. 2005. On the locality of left branch extraction and the structure of
NP. Studia Linguistica 59: 1-45.
Bošković, Željko. 2008. What will you have, DP or NP? In Proceedings of FASL 6.5: 9-
35.
Bosque, Ignacio and Carme Picallo. 1996. Postnominal adjectives in Spanish DPs.
Journal of Linguistics 32: 349-385.
Brugè, Laura. 2002. The positions of demonstratives in the extended nominal
projection. In Functional structure in DP and IP: The cartography of syntactic
structures, ed. Guglielmo Cinque, 15-53. Oxford and New York: Oxford
University Press.
Chierchia, Gennaro. 1998. Reference to kinds across languages. Natural Language
Semantics 6: 339-405.
Chomsky, Noam. 1957. Syntactic structures. The Hague: Mouton.
Chomsky, Noam. 1970. Remarks on nominalization. In Readings in English
Transformational Grammar. eds. Roderick A. Jacob and Peter S. Rosenbaum,
184-221. Waltham: Ginn.
Chomsky, Noam. 1981. Lectures on Government and Binding. Mouton de Gruyter
Chomsky, Noam. 1986. Barriers (Linguistic Inquiry monographs: 13). Cambridge,
Massachusetts: The Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.
91
Chomsky, Noam. 1995a. The minimalist program (Current studies in linguistics: 28).
Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.
Chomsky, Noam.1995b. Bare phrase structure . In Government and Binding theory and
the Minimalist Program, ed. Gert Webelhuth, 383-439. Oxford and Cambridge,
Massachusetts: Basil Blackwell.
Chomsky, Noam. 2000. Minimalist inquiries: The Framework. In Step by step: Essays
on minimalist syntax in honor of Howard Lasnik. eds. Roger Martin, David
Michaels and Juan Uriagereka, 89-155. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The
Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.
Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Ken Hale: A Life in Language, ed.
Michael Kenstowicz, 1-52. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Massachusetts
Institute of Technology Press.
Cinque, Guglielmo. 1994. On the evidence for partial N movement in the Romance DP.
In Paths towards universal grammar: Studies in honor of Richard S. Kayne. eds.
Guglielmo Cinque, Jan Koster, Jean-Yves Pollock, Luigi Rizzi and Raffaella
Zanuttini, 85-110.Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.
Corver, Norbert. 1992. On deriving certain left branch extraction asymmetries: A case
study in parametric syntax. In NELS 22: proceedings of the twenty-second annual
meeting of the North East Linguistic Society, ed. Kimberly Broderick, 67-84.
Amhest: Graduate Linguistics Students Association, University of Massachusetts.
Dobrovie-Sorin, Carmen. 1987. A propos de la structure du groupe nominal en roumain.
Rivista di grammatica generativa 12: 123-152.
Duffield, Nigel. 1995. Particles and Projections in Irish Syntax. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
92
Engelhardt, Miriam and Helen Trugman. 1998. D as a source of adnominal genitive in
Russian. In Formal approaches to Slavic linguistics: The Connecticut meeting
1997 (Michigan Slavic materials: 43), eds. Željko Bošković, Steven Franks and
William Snyder, 114-133. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic Publications.
Fanselow, Gisbert and Damir Ćavar. 2002. Distributed deletion. In Theoretical
approaches to universals, ed. Artemis Alexiadou, 65-107. Amsterdam,
Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
Fukui, Naoki. 1986. A theory of category projection and its applications. Doctoral
dissertation. The Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
Gedeon, Olexandra. 2004. Ukrainian possessives and the uniqueness of the third person
possessive pronouns. Colloquium Talks. Detroit: Wayne State University.
Giusti, Giuliana. 1991. The categorial status of quantified nominals, Liguistishe
Berichte 136: 438-454.
Giusti, Giuliana. 1994. Heads and Modifiers among Determiners. In Advance in
Romanian Linguistics, Linguistik Aktuell 10, eds. Cinque Guglielmo and Giuliana
Giusti, 103-125. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Giusti, Giuliana. 1995. A unified structural representation of (abstract) case and article.
Evidence from Germanic. In Studies in comparative Germanic syntax, eds. Hubert
Haider, Susan Olsen and Sten Vikner, 77-93. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Giusti, Giuliana. 1997. The categorial status of determiners. In The new comparative
syntax, ed. Liliane Haegeman, 95-123. London: Longman.
Giusti, Giuliana. 2002. The functional structure of noun phrases: A bare phrase structure
approach. In Functional structure in DP and IP: the cartography of syntactic
93
structures, vol. 1, ed. Guglielmo Cinque, 54-90. Oxfordand New York: Oxford
University Press.
Giusti, Giuliana and Nedžad Leko. 1995. On the syntax of quantity expressions in
Bosnian. University of Venice Working Papers in Linguistics 5.2: 23-47.
Grohmann, Kleanthes K. and Phoevos Panagiotidis. 2004. Demonstrative doubling in
Greek. In University of Maryland working papers in linguistics 13, eds. Pritha
Chandra, Tomohiro Fujii, Usama Soltan and Masaya Yoshida, 109-131. College
Park: Department of Linguistics, University of Maryland.
Grosu, Alexander. 1988. On the distribution of genitive phrases in Rumanian.
Linguistics 26: 931- 949.
Haegeman, Liliane. 1997. The New Comparative Syntax. London: Longman.
Haegeman, Liliane and Jacqueline Guéron. 1999. English grammar: A generative
perspective. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.
Hammarström, Harald. 2004. Properties of lower numerals and their explanation: a
reply to Paweł Rutkowski. Journal of Universal Language 5.2: 1-20.
Hornstein, Norbert, Jairo Nunes, Kleanthes K. Grohmann. 2005. Understanding
Minimalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Jackendoff, Ray. S. 1977. X’ syntax: A study of phrase structure. Cambridge,
Massachusetts: The Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.
Julien, Marit. 2002. Determiners and word order in Scandinavian DPs. Studia
Linguistica 56: 264-315.
Kim, Ji-yung. 2004. Specific nominals in Chinese and Korean. Language and
Linguistics 5.1: 243-270.
Larson, Richard K. 1987. 'Missing prepositions' and the analysis of English free relative
clauses. Linguistic Inquiry 16: 239-266.
94
Larson, Richard K. 1988. On the double object construction. Linguistic Inquiry 19,
335-391.
Lecko, Nedžad. 1999. Funcional categories and the structure of DP in Bosnian. In
Mechanisms of syntactic change, eds. Mila Dimitrova-Vulchanova and Lars
Hellan, 419- 444. Austin, University of Texas Press.
Linde-Usiekniewicz, Jadwiga. and Paweł Rutkowski. 2007b. NP coordination as a new
argument in the debate on the DP-analysis of Polish. In LSO working papers in
linguistics, vol. 6: Proceedings of WIGL 2006, ed. Blake H. Rodgers, 103-116
Madison: Department of Linguistics, University of Wisconsin-Madison.
Linde-Usiekniewicz, Jadwiga and Pawel Rutkowski. 2007a. Frequency of use of Polish
numerals does not influence their syntax. In Simon Fraser University working
papers in linguistics, vol. 1: Proceedings of the 22nd NorthWest Linguistics
Conference (NWLC22), eds. Nicole Carter, Loreley Hadic-Zabala, Anne Rimrott
and Dennis Ryan Storoshenko, 175-186. Burnaby: SFU Linguistics Graduate
Students’ Association, Simon Fraser University.
Longobardi, Giuseppe. 1994. Reference and proper names: A theory of N-movement in
syntax and Logical Form. Linguistic Inquiry 25: 609-665.
Longobardi, Giuseppe. 2001. The structure of DPs: Some principles, parameters, and
problems. In The handbook of contemporary syntactic theory, eds. Mark Baltin
and Chris Collins, 562-603. Malden, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Longobardi, Giuseppe. 2006. Reference to individuals, person, and the variety of
mapping parameters. Trieste: Uiniversità degli Studi di Trieste.
Lyons, Christopher. 1997. Definiteness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Megerdoomian, Karine. 2008. Parallel Nominal and Verbal Projections. In
Foundational Issues in Linguistic Theory: Essays in Honor of Jean-Roger
95
Vergnaud, eds. Robert Freidin, Carlos P. Otero and Maria Luisa Zubizarreta, 73-
103. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Massachusetts Institute of Technology
Press.
Migdalski, Krzysztof. 2000. The Determiner Phrase hypothesis in Polish. MA thesis,
Wrocław: Uniwersytet Wrocławski.
Mohammad, M. 1988. The Sentential Structure of Arabic. Doctoral dissertation,
University of Southern California.
Pereltsvaig, Asya. 2007. The universality of DP: A view from Russian. Studia
Linguistica 61: 59-94.
Progovac, Ljiljana. 1998. Determiner Phrase in a language without determiners.
Journal of Linguistics 34: 165-179.
Radford, Andrew. 1988. Transformational Grammar: A First Course. Cambridge
University Press.
Radford, Aandrew. 1997. Syntactic theory and the structure of English: a minimalist
approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Radford, Andrew. 2000. NP shells. Essex Research Reports in Linguistics 33: 2-20.
Radford, Andrew. 2004. Minimalist Syntax: Exploring the structure of English.
Cambridge : Cambridge University Press.
Ritter, E. 1988. A head-movement approach to construct-state noun phrases. Linguistics
26: 909-929.
Ritter, Elizabeth. 1991. Two functional categories in noun phrases: Evidence from
Modern Hebrew. In Syntax and semantics 25, Perspectives on phrase structure:
Heads and licensing, ed. Susan D. Rothstein, 37-62, San Diego: Academic Press.
96
Ritter, Elizabeth. 1992. Cross-linguistic evidence for number phrase. Canadian Journal
of Linguistics 37: 197-218.
Roehrs, Dorian. 2006. The morpho-syntax of the Germanic noun phrase: Determiners
move into the Determiner Phrase. Doctoral dissertation. Bloomington: Indiana
University.
Rutkowski, Paweł. 2000. Składnia polskich grup liczebnikowych: Próba opisu
formalnego. Poradnik Językowy 8: 10-28.
Rutkowski, Paweł. 2001. Numeral Phrases in Polish and Estonian. In Proceedings of the
18th Scandinavian Conference of Linguistics 2, eds. Arthur Holmer, Jan-Olof
Svantesson and Åke Viberg, 181-190. Lund: Lund University Press.
Rutkowski, Paweł. 2002a. The syntax of Quantifier Phrases and the inherent vs.
structural case distinction. Linguistic Research 7.1: 43-74.
Rutkowski, Paweł. 2002b. Noun/pronoun asymmetries: Evidence in support of the DP
hypothesis in Polish. In ADL'2002: Actes des 7e rencontres de l'atelier des
doctorants en linguistique, eds. Peggy Afuta, Adil El Ghali and François
Toussenel, 91-96. Paris: École Doctorale de Sciences du Langage, Université
Paris 7.
Rutkowski, Paweł. 2002c. Noun/pronoun asymmetries: Evidence in support of the DP
hypothesis in Polish. Jezikoslovlje 3.1-2: 159-170.
Rutkowski, Paweł. 2007a. The syntax of floating intensifiers in Polish and its
implications for the Determiner Phrase hypothesis. In Proceedings of the Thirty-
Second Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society, eds. Zhenya Antic,
Molly Babel, Charles Chang, Jisup Hong, Michael Houser, Fang-Chun Liu,
Maziar Toosarvandani and Yao Yao. Berkeley: University of California
97
Rutkowski, Paweł. 2007b. Hipoteza frazy przedimkowej jako narzędzie opisu
składniowego polskich grup imiennych. Doctral dissertation. Warszawa:
Uniwersytet Warszawski.
Rutkowski, Paweł. 2009. Fraza przedimkowa w polszczyźnie. Warszawa: Wydział
Polonistyki Uniwersytetu Warszawskiego.
Rutkowski, Pawel and Ljiljana Progovac. 2005. Classification Projection in Polish and
Serbian: The position and shape of classifying adjectives. In Formal approaches
to Slavic linguistics: The South Carolina meeting 2004, eds. Steven Franks, Frank
Y. Gladney and Mila Tasseva-Kurktchieva, 289-299. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic
Publications.
Scott, Gray-John. 2002. Stacked adjectival modification and the structure of nominal
phrases. In Functional structure in DP and IP: The cartography of syntactic
structures, ed. Guglielmo Cinque, 91-120. Oxford, New York: Oxford University
Press.
Sio, Joanna Ut-seong. 2006. Modification and reference in the Chinese nominal.
Utrecht: LOT – Landelijke Onderzoekschool Taalwetenschap.
Speas, Margaret J. 1990. Phrase structure in natural language. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Szabolcsi, Anna. 1984. The possessor that run away from home. The Linguistic Review
3: 89-102.
Szabolcsi, Anna. 1987. Functional categories in the noun phrase. In Approaches to
Hungarian, Theories and analyses, ed. István Kenesei, 167-189. Szeged: József
Attila Tudományegyetem (JATE).
Szabolcsi, Anna. 1994. The Noun Phrase. In The Syntactic Structure of Hungarian. eds.
Ferenc Kiefer and Katalin E. Kiss, 179-274. San Diego and New York; Academic
Press.
98
Travis, Lisa. 1992. Inner Tense with NPs: The Position of Number. In 1992 Annual
Conference of the Canadian Linguistics association, 329-345. Toronto: University
of Toronto Working Papers in Linguistics.
Valois, Daniel. 1991. The internal syntax of DP. Doctoral dissertation. Los Angeles:
University of California.
Veselovská, Ludmila. 1995. Phrasal movement and X
0
-morphology: Word order
parallels in Czech and English. Doctoral dissertation. Univerzita Palackého v
Olomouci.
Willim, Ewa. 2000. On the grammar of Polish nominals. In Step by step: Essays on
minimalist syntax in honor of Howard Lasnik, eds. Roger Martin, David Michaels
and Juan Uriagereka, 319-346. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Massachusetts
Institute of Technology Press.
Yadroff, Michael. 1999. Formal properties of functional categories: The minimalist
syntax of Russian nominal and Prepositional expressions. Doctoral dissertation.
Bloomington: Indiana University.
Zlatić, Larisa. 1997. The structure of the Serbian noun phrase. Doctoral dissertation.
Austin: University of Texas.