THE ESSAYS
OF
ARTHUR SCHOPENHAUER
TRANSL
TRANSL
TRANSL
TRANSL
TRANSLA
A
A
A
ATED BY
TED BY
TED BY
TED BY
TED BY
T
T
T
T
T. BAILE
. BAILE
. BAILE
. BAILE
. BAILEY SA
Y SA
Y SA
Y SA
Y SAUNDERS, M.A.
UNDERS, M.A.
UNDERS, M.A.
UNDERS, M.A.
UNDERS, M.A.
V
V
V
V
Volume O
olume O
olume O
olume O
olume One
ne
ne
ne
ne
COUNSELS AND MAXIMS
A
N
E
LECTRONIC
C
LASSICS
S
ERIES
P
UBLICATION
The Essays of Arthur Schopenhauer: Counsels and Maxims (Volume One) trans. T. Bailey Saunders
is a publication of The Electronic Classics Series. This Portable Document file is furnished free
and without any charge of any kind. Any person using this document file, for any purpose, and
in any way does so at his or her own risk. Neither the Pennsylvania State University nor Jim
Manis, Editor, nor anyone associated with the Pennsylvania State University assumes any re-
sponsibility for the material contained within the document or for the file as an electronic
transmission, in any way.
The Essays of Arthur Schopenhauer: Counsels and Maxims (Volume One) trans. T. Bailey Saunders,
The Electronic Classics Series, Jim Manis, Editor, PSU-Hazleton, Hazleton, PA 18202 is a Portable
Document File produced as part of an ongoing publication project to bring classical works of
literature, in English, to free and easy access of those wishing to make use of them.
Jim Manis is a faculty member of the English Department of The Pennsylvania State University. This
page and any preceding page(s) are restricted by copyright. The text of the following pages is not
copyrighted within the United States; however, the fonts used may be.
Cover Design: Jim Manis
Copyright © 2004 - 2013
The Pennsylvania State University is an equal opportunity university.
Contents
4
Essays – Volume One
THE ESSAYS
OF
ARTHUR
SCHOPENHAUER
TRANSL
TRANSL
TRANSL
TRANSL
TRANSLA
A
A
A
ATED BY
TED BY
TED BY
TED BY
TED BY
T
T
T
T
T. BAILE
. BAILE
. BAILE
. BAILE
. BAILEY SA
Y SA
Y SA
Y SA
Y SAUNDERS, M.A.
UNDERS, M.A.
UNDERS, M.A.
UNDERS, M.A.
UNDERS, M.A.
V
V
V
V
Volume O
olume O
olume O
olume O
olume One
ne
ne
ne
ne
COUNSELS AND MAXIMS
Le bonheur n’est pas chose aisée: il est
très difficile de le trouver en nous, et impossible
de le trouver ailleurs.
—CHAMFORT.
INTR
INTR
INTR
INTR
INTRODUCTION
ODUCTION
ODUCTION
ODUCTION
ODUCTION
I
F
MY
OBJECT
in these pages were to present a complete scheme
of counsels and maxims for the guidance of life, I should
have to repeat the numerous rules—some of them excellent—
which have been drawn up by thinkers of all ages, from
Theognis and Solomon
1
down to La Rochefoucauld; and,
in so doing, I should inevitably entail upon the reader a vast
amount of well-worn commonplace. But the fact is that in
this work I make still less claim to exhaust my subject than
in any other of my writings.
1 I refer to the proverbs and maxims ascribed, in the Old
Testament, to the king of that name.
5
Schopenhauer
An author who makes no claims to completeness must also,
in a great measure, abandon any attempt at systematic ar-
rangement. For his double loss in this respect, the reader
may console himself by reflecting that a complete and sys-
tematic treatment of such a subject as the guidance of life
could hardly fail to be a very wearisome business. I have sim-
ply put down those of my thoughts which appear to be worth
communicating—thoughts which, as far as I know, have not
been uttered, or, at any rate, not just in the same form, by
any one else; so that my remarks may be taken as a supple-
ment to what has been already achieved in the immense field.
However, by way of introducing some sort of order into
the great variety of matters upon which advice will be given
in the following pages, I shall distribute what I have to say
under the following heads: (1) general rules; (2) our relation
to ourselves; (3) our relation to others; and finally, (4) rules
which concern our manner of life and our worldly circum-
stances. I shall conclude with some remarks on the changes
which the various periods of life produce in us.
CHAPTER I
CHAPTER I
CHAPTER I
CHAPTER I
CHAPTER I
GENERAL R
GENERAL R
GENERAL R
GENERAL R
GENERAL RULES.—SECTION 1.
ULES.—SECTION 1.
ULES.—SECTION 1.
ULES.—SECTION 1.
ULES.—SECTION 1.
T
HE
FIRST
AND
FOREMOST
RULE
for the wise conduct of life
seems to me to be contained in a view to which Aristotle
parenthetically refers in the Nichomachean Ethics:
1
[Greek:
o phronimoz to alupon dioke e ou to aedu] or, as it may be
rendered, not pleasure, but freedom from pain, is what the wise
man will aim at.
The truth of this remark turns upon the negative character
of happiness,—the fact that pleasure is only the negation of
pain, and that pain is the positive element in life. Though I
have given a detailed proof of this proposition in my chief
work,
2
I may supply one more illustration of it here, drawn
from a circumstance of daily occurrence. Suppose that, with
the exception of some sore or painful spot, we are physically
in a sound and healthy condition: the sore of this one spot,
will completely absorb our attention, causing us to lose the
1 vii. (12) 12.
2 Welt als Wille und Vorstellung. Vol. I., p. 58.
6
Essays – Volume One
sense of general well-being, and destroying all our comfort
in life. In the same way, when all our affairs but one turn out
as we wish, the single instance in which our aims are frus-
trated is a constant trouble to us, even though it be some-
thing quite trivial. We think a great deal about it, and very
little about those other and more important matters in which
we have been successful. In both these cases what has met
with resistance is the will; in the one case, as it is objectified
in the organism, in the other, as it presents itself in the struggle
of life; and in both, it is plain that the satisfaction of the will
consists in nothing else than that it meets with no resistance.
It is, therefore, a satisfaction which is not directly felt; at
most, we can become conscious of it only when we reflect
upon our condition. But that which checks or arrests the
will is something positive; it proclaims its own presence. All
pleasure consists in merely removing this check—in other
words, in freeing us from its action; and hence pleasure is a
state which can never last very long.
This is the true basis of the above excellent rule quoted
from Aristotle, which bids us direct our aim, not toward se-
curing what is pleasurable and agreeable in life, but toward
avoiding, as far as possible, its innumerable evils. If this were
not the right course to take, that saying of Voltaire’s, Happi-
ness is but a dream and sorrow is real, would be as false as it is,
in fact, true. A man who desires to make up the book of his
life and determine where the balance of happiness lies, must
put down in his accounts, not the pleasures which he has
enjoyed, but the evils which he has escaped. That is the true
method of eudaemonology; for all eudaemonology must
begin by recognizing that its very name is a euphemism, and
that to live happily only means to live less unhappily—to live
a tolerable life. There is no doubt that life is given us, not to
be enjoyed, but to be overcome—to be got over. There are
numerous expressions illustrating this—such as degere vitam,
vita defungi; or in Italian, si scampa cosi; or in German, man
muss suchen durchzukommen; er wird schon durch die Welt
kommen, and so on. In old age it is indeed a consolation to
think that the work of life is over and done with. The happi-
est lot is not to have experienced the keenest delights or the
greatest pleasures, but to have brought life to a close without
any very great pain, bodily or mental. To measure the happi-
ness of a life by its delights or pleasures, is to apply a false
7
Schopenhauer
standard. For pleasures are and remain something negative;
that they produce happiness is a delusion, cherished by envy
to its own punishment. Pain is felt to be something positive,
and hence its absence is the true standard of happiness. And
if, over and above freedom from pain, there is also an ab-
sence of boredom, the essential conditions of earthly happi-
ness are attained; for all else is chimerical.
It follows from this that a man should never try to pur-
chase pleasure at the cost of pain, or even at the risk of incur-
ring it; to do so is to pay what is positive and real, for what is
negative and illusory; while there is a net profit in sacrificing
pleasure for the sake of avoiding pain. In either case it is a
matter of indifference whether the pain follows the pleasure
or precedes it. While it is a complete inversion of the natural
order to try and turn this scene of misery into a garden of
pleasure, to aim at joy and pleasure rather than at the great-
est possible freedom from pain—and yet how many do it!—
there is some wisdom in taking a gloomy view, in looking
upon the world as a kind of Hell, and in confining one’s
efforts to securing a little room that shall not be exposed to
the fire. The fool rushes after the pleasures of life and finds
himself their dupe; the wise man avoids its evils; and even if,
notwithstanding his precautions, he falls into misfortunes,
that is the fault of fate, not of his own folly. As far as he is
successful in his endeavors, he cannot be said to have lived a
life of illusion; for the evils which he shuns are very real.
Even if he goes too far out of his way to avoid evils, and
makes an unnecessary sacrifice of pleasure, he is, in reality,
not the worse off for that; for all pleasures are chimerical,
and to mourn for having lost any of them is a frivolous, and
even ridiculous proceeding.
The failure to recognize this truth—a failure promoted by
optimistic ideas—is the source of much unhappiness. In
moments free from pain, our restless wishes present, as it
were in a mirror, the image of a happiness that has no coun-
terpart in reality, seducing us to follow it; in doing so we
bring pain upon ourselves, and that is something undeni-
ably real. Afterwards, we come to look with regret upon that
lost state of painlessness; it is a paradise which we have
gambled away; it is no longer with us, and we long in vain to
undo what has been done.
One might well fancy that these visions of wishes fulfilled
8
Essays – Volume One
were the work of some evil spirit, conjured up in order to
entice us away from that painless state which forms our high-
est happiness.
A careless youth may think that the world is meant to be
enjoyed, as though it were the abode of some real or positive
happiness, which only those fail to attain who are not clever
enough to overcome the difficulties that lie in the way. This
false notion takes a stronger hold on him when he comes to
read poetry and romance, and to be deceived by outward
show—the hypocrisy that characterizes the world from be-
ginning to end; on which I shall have something to say pres-
ently. The result is that his life is the more or less deliberate
pursuit of positive happiness; and happiness he takes to be
equivalent to a series of definite pleasures. In seeking for these
pleasures he encounters danger—a fact which should not be
forgotten. He hunts for game that does not exist; and so he
ends by suffering some very real and positive misfortune—
pain, distress, sickness, loss, care, poverty, shame, and all the
thousand ills of life. Too late he discovers the trick that has
been played upon him.
But if the rule I have mentioned is observed, and a plan of
life is adopted which proceeds by avoiding pain—in other
words, by taking measures of precaution against want, sick-
ness, and distress in all its forms, the aim is a real one, and
something may be achieved which will be great in propor-
tion as the plan is not disturbed by striving after the chimera
of positive happiness. This agrees with the opinion expressed
by Goethe in the Elective Affinities, and there put into the
mouth of Mittler—the man who is always trying to make
other people happy: To desire to get rid of an evil is a definite
object, but to desire a better fortune than one has is blind folly.
The same truth is contained in that fine French proverb: le
mieux est l’ennemi du bien—leave well alone. And, as I have
remarked in my chief work,
1
this is the leading thought
underlying the philosophical system of the Cynics. For what
was it led the Cynics to repudiate pleasure in every form, if it
was not the fact that pain is, in a greater or less degree, al-
ways bound up with pleasure? To go out of the way of pain
seemed to them so much easier than to secure pleasure.
Deeply impressed as they were by the negative nature of plea-
sure and the positive nature of pain, they consistently de-
1 Welt als Wille und Vorstellung, vol. ii., ch. 16.
9
Schopenhauer
voted all their efforts to the avoidance of pain. The first step
to that end was, in their opinion, a complete and deliberate
repudiation of pleasure, as something which served only to
entrap the victim in order that he might be delivered over to
pain.
We are all born, as Schiller says, in Arcadia. In other words,
we come into the world full of claims to happiness and plea-
sure, and we cherish the fond hope of making them good.
But, as a rule, Fate soon teaches us, in a rough and ready way
that we really possess nothing at all, but that everything in
the world is at its command, in virtue of an unassailable
right, not only to all we have or acquire, to wife or child, but
even to our very limbs, our arms, legs, eyes and ears, nay,
even to the nose in the middle of our face. And in any case,
after some little time, we learn by experience that happiness
and pleasure are a fata morgana, which, visible from afar,
vanish as we approach; that, on the other hand, suffering
and pain are a reality, which makes its presence felt without
any intermediary, and for its effect, stands in no need of
illusion or the play of false hope.
If the teaching of experience bears fruit in us, we soon give
up the pursuit of pleasure and happiness, and think much
more about making ourselves secure against the attacks of
pain and suffering. We see that the best the world has to
offer is an existence free from pain—a quiet, tolerable life;
and we confine our claims to this, as to something we can
more surely hope to achieve. For the safest way of not being
very miserable is not to expect to be very happy. Merck, the
friend of Goethe’s youth, was conscious of this truth when
he wrote: It is the wretched way people have of setting up a
claim to happiness—and, that to, in a measure corresponding
with their desires—that ruins everything in this world. A man
will make progress if he can get rid of this claim,
1
and desire
nothing but what he sees before him. Accordingly it is advis-
able to put very moderate limits upon our expectations of
pleasure, possessions, rank, honor and so on; because it is
just this striving and struggling to be happy, to dazzle the
world, to lead a life full of pleasure, which entail great mis-
fortune. It is prudent and wise, I say, to reduce one’s claims,
if only for the reason that it is extremely easy to be very
unhappy; while to be very happy is not indeed difficult, but
1 Letters to and from Merck.
10
Essays – Volume One
quite impossible. With justice sings the poet of life’s wis-
dom:
Auream quisquis mediocritatem
Diligit, tutus caret obsoleti
Sordibus tecti, caret invidenda
Sobrius aula.
Savius ventis agitatur ingens
Pinus: et celsae graviori casu
Decidunt turres; feriuntque summos
Fulgura monies.
2
—the golden mean is best—to live free from the squalor of a
mean abode, and yet not be a mark for envy. It is the tall
pine which is cruelly shaken by the wind, the highest sum-
mits that are struck in the storm, and the lofty towers that
fall so heavily.
He who has taken to heart the teaching of my philoso-
phy—who knows, therefore, that our whole existence is some-
thing which had better not have been, and that to disown
and disclaim it is the highest wisdom—he will have no great
expectations from anything or any condition in life: he will
spend passion upon nothing in the world, nor lament over-
much if he fails in any of his undertakings. He will feel the
deep truth of what Plato
1
says: [Greek: oute ti ton
anthropinon haxion on megalaes spondaes]—nothing in
human affairs is worth any great anxiety; or, as the Persian
poet has it,
Though from thy grasp all worldly things should flee,
Grieve not for them, for they are nothing worth:
And though a world in thy possession be,
Joy not, for worthless are the things of earth.
Since to that better world ’tis given to thee
To pass, speed on, for this is nothing worth.
2
The chief obstacle to our arriving at these salutary views
is that hypocrisy of the world to which I have already al-
2 Horace. Odes II. x.
1 Republic, x. 604.
2 Translator’s Note. From the Anvár-i Suhailí—The Lights of
Canopus—being the Persian version of the Table of Bidpai.
Translated by E.B. Eastwick, ch. iii. Story vi., p. 289.
11
Schopenhauer
luded—an hypocrisy which should be early revealed to the
young. Most of the glories of the world are mere outward
show, like the scenes on a stage: there is nothing real about
them. Ships festooned and hung with pennants, firing of
cannon, illuminations, beating of drums and blowing of
trumpets, shouting and applauding—these are all the out-
ward sign, the pretence and suggestion,—as it were the hi-
eroglyphic,—of joy: but just there, joy is, as a rule, not to
be found; it is the only guest who has declined to be present
at the festival. Where this guest may really be found, he
comes generally without invitation; he is not formerly an-
nounced, but slips in quietly by himself sans facon; often
making his appearance under the most unimportant and
trivial circumstances, and in the commonest company—
anywhere, in short, but where the society is brilliant and
distinguished. Joy is like the gold in the Australian mines—
found only now and then, as it were, by the caprice of
chance, and according to no rule or law; oftenest in very
little grains, and very seldom in heaps. All that outward
show which I have described, is only an attempt to make
people believe that it is really joy which has come to the
festival; and to produce this impression upon the specta-
tors is, in fact, the whole object of it.
With mourning it is just the same. That long funeral pro-
cession, moving up so slowly; how melancholy it looks! what
an endless row of carriages! But look into them—they are all
empty; the coachmen of the whole town are the sole escort
the dead man has to his grave. Eloquent picture of the friend-
ship and esteem of the world! This is the falsehood, the hol-
lowness, the hypocrisy of human affairs!
Take another example—a roomful of guests in full dress,
being received with great ceremony. You could almost be-
lieve that this is a noble and distinguished company; but, as
a matter of fact, it is compulsion, pain and boredom who are
the real guests. For where many are invited, it is a rabble—
even if they all wear stars. Really good society is everywhere
of necessity very small. In brilliant festivals and noisy enter-
tainments, there is always, at bottom, a sense of emptiness
prevalent. A false tone is there: such gatherings are in strange
contrast with the misery and barrenness of our existence.
The contrast brings the true condition into greater relief.
Still, these gatherings are effective from the outside; and that
12
Essays – Volume One
is just their purpose. Chamfort
1
makes the excellent remark
that society—les cercles, les salons, ce qu’on appelle le monde—
is like a miserable play, or a bad opera, without any interest
in itself, but supported for a time by mechanical aid, cos-
tumes and scenery.
And so, too, with academies and chairs of philosophy. You
have a kind of sign-board hung out to show the apparent
abode of wisdom: but wisdom is another guest who declines
the invitation; she is to be found elsewhere. The chiming of
bells, ecclesiastical millinery, attitudes of devotion, insane
antics—these are the pretence, the false show of piety. And
so on. Everything in the world is like a hollow nut; there is
little kernel anywhere, and when it does exist, it is still more
rare to find it in the shell. You may look for it elsewhere, and
find it, as a rule, only by chance.
SECTION 2. To estimate a man’s condition in regard to
happiness, it is necessary to ask, not what things please him,
but what things trouble him; and the more trivial these things
are in themselves, the happier the man will be. To be irri-
tated by trifles, a man must be well off; for in misfortunes
trifles are unfelt.
SECTION 3. Care should be taken not to build the happi-
ness of life upon a broad foundation—not to require a great
many things in order to be happy. For happiness on such a
foundation is the most easily undermined; it offers many
more opportunities for accidents; and accidents are always
happening. The architecture of happiness follows a plan in
this respect just the opposite of that adopted in every other
case, where the broadest foundation offers the greatest secu-
rity. Accordingly, to reduce your claims to the lowest pos-
sible degree, in comparison with your means,—of whatever
kind these may be—is the surest way of avoiding extreme
misfortune.
To make extensive preparations for life—no matter what
form they may take—is one of the greatest and commonest
of follies. Such preparations presuppose, in the first place, a
1 Translator’s Note. Nicholas “Chamfort” (1741-94), a French
miscellaneous writer, whose brilliant conversation, power of
sarcasm, and epigrammic force, coupled with an extraordi-
nary career, render him one of the most interesting and re-
markable men of his time. Schopenhauer undoubtedly owed
much to this writer, to whom he constantly refers.
13
Schopenhauer
long life, the full and complete term of years appointed to
man—and how few reach it! and even if it be reached, it is
still too short for all the plans that have been made; for to
carry them out requites more time than was thought neces-
sary at the beginning. And then how many mischances and
obstacles stand in the way! how seldom the goal is ever reached
in human affairs!
And lastly, even though the goal should be reached, the
changes which Time works in us have been left out of the
reckoning: we forget that the capacity whether for achieve-
ment or for enjoyment does not last a whole lifetime. So we
often toil for things which are no longer suited to us when
we attain them; and again, the years we spend in preparing
for some work, unconsciously rob us of the power for carry-
ing it out.
How often it happens that a man is unable to enjoy the
wealth which he acquired at so much trouble and risk, and
that the fruits of his labor are reserved for others; or that he
is incapable of filling the position which he has won after so
many years of toil and struggle. Fortune has come too late
for him; or, contrarily, he has come too late for fortune,—
when, for instance, he wants to achieve great things, say, in
art or literature: the popular taste has changed, it may be; a
new generation has grown up, which takes no interest in his
work; others have gone a shorter way and got the start of
him. These are the facts of life which Horace must have had
in view, when he lamented the uselessness of all advice:—
quid eternis minorem
Consiliis animum fatigas?
1
The cause of this commonest of all follies is that optical illu-
sion of the mind from which everyone suffers, making life,
at its beginning, seem of long duration; and at its end, when
one looks back over the course of it, how short a time it
seems! There is some advantage in the illusion; but for it, no
great work would ever be done.
Our life is like a journey on which, as we advance, the
landscape takes a different view from that which it presented
at first, and changes again, as we come nearer. This is just
what happens—especially with our wishes. We often find
1 Odes II. xi.
14
Essays – Volume One
something else, nay, something better than what we are look-
ing for; and what we look for, we often find on a very differ-
ent path from that on which we began a vain search. Instead
of finding, as we expected, pleasure, happiness, joy, we get
experience, insight, knowledge—a real and permanent bless-
ing, instead of a fleeting and illusory one.
This is the thought that runs through Wilkelm Meister, like
the bass in a piece of music. In this work of Goethe’s, we
have a novel of the intellectual kind, and, therefore, superior
to all others, even to Sir Walter Scott’s, which are, one and
all, ethical; in other words, they treat of human nature only
from the side of the will. So, too, in the Zauberflöte—that
grotesque, but still significant, and even hieroglyphic—the
same thought is symbolized, but in great, coarse lines, much
in the way in which scenery is painted. Here the symbol
would be complete if Tamino were in the end to be cured of
his desire to possess Tainina, and received, in her stead, ini-
tiation into the mysteries of the Temple of Wisdom. It is
quite right for Papageno, his necessary contrast, to succeed
in getting his Papagena.
Men of any worth or value soon come to see that they are
in the hands of Fate, and gratefully submit to be moulded by
its teachings. They recognize that the fruit of life is experi-
ence, and not happiness; they become accustomed and con-
tent to exchange hope for insight; and, in the end, they can
say, with Petrarch, that all they care for is to learn:—
Altro diletto che ‘mparar, non provo.
It may even be that they to some extent still follow their old
wishes and aims, trifling with them, as it were, for the sake
of appearances; all the while really and seriously looking for
nothing but instruction; a process which lends them an air
of genius, a trait of something contemplative and sublime.
In their search for gold, the alchemists discovered other
things—gunpowder, china, medicines, the laws of nature.
There is a sense in which we are all alchemists.
15
Schopenhauer
CHAPTER II
CHAPTER II
CHAPTER II
CHAPTER II
CHAPTER II
OUR REL
OUR REL
OUR REL
OUR REL
OUR RELA
A
A
A
ATION
TION
TION
TION
TION T
T
T
T
TO OURSEL
O OURSEL
O OURSEL
O OURSEL
O OURSELVES.—SECTION 4.
VES.—SECTION 4.
VES.—SECTION 4.
VES.—SECTION 4.
VES.—SECTION 4.
T
HE
MASON
EMPLOYED
on the building of a house may be
quite ignorant of its general design; or at any rate, he may
not keep it constantly in mind. So it is with man: in working
through the days and hours of his life, he takes little thought
of its character as a whole.
If there is any merit or importance attaching to a man’s
career, if he lays himself out carefully for some special work,
it is all the more necessary and advisable for him to turn his
attention now and then to its plan, that is to say, the minia-
ture sketch of its general outlines. Of course, to do that, he
must have applied the maxim [Greek: Gnothi seauton]; he
must have made some little progress in the art of under-
standing himself. He must know what is his real, chief, and
foremost object in life,—what it is that he most wants in
order to be happy; and then, after that, what occupies the
second and third place in his thoughts; he must find out
what, on the whole, his vocation really is—the part he has to
play, his general relation to the world. If he maps out impor-
tant work for himself on great lines, a glance at this minia-
ture plan of his life will, more than anything else stimulate,
rouse and ennoble him, urge him on to action and keep him
from false paths.
Again, just as the traveler, on reaching a height, gets a con-
nected view over the road he has taken, with its many turns
and windings; so it is only when we have completed a period
in our life, or approach the end of it altogether, that we rec-
ognize the true connection between all our actions,—what
it is we have achieved, what work we have done. It is only
then that we see the precise chain of cause and effect, and
the exact value of all our efforts. For as long as we are actu-
ally engaged in the work of life, we always act in accordance
with the nature of our character, under the influence of mo-
tive, and within the limits of our capacity,—in a word, from
beginning to end, under a law of necessity; at every moment
we do just what appears to us right and proper. It is only
afterwards, when we come to look back at the whole course
of our life and its general result, that we see the why and
wherefore of it all.
16
Essays – Volume One
When we are actually doing some great deed, or creating
some immortal work, we are not conscious of it as such; we
think only of satisfying present aims, of fulfilling the inten-
tions we happen to have at the time, of doing the right thing
at the moment. It is only when we come to view our life as a
connected whole that our character and capacities show them-
selves in their true light; that we see how, in particular in-
stances, some happy inspiration, as it were, led us to choose
the only true path out of a thousand which might have
brought us to ruin. It was our genius that guided us, a force
felt in the affairs of the intellectual as in those of the world;
and working by its defect just in the same way in regard to
evil and disaster.
SECTION 5. Another important element in the wise con-
duct of life is to preserve a proper proportion between our
thought for the present and our thought for the future; in
order not to spoil the one by paying over-great attention to
the other. Many live too long in the present—frivolous
people, I mean; others, too much in the future, ever anxious
and full of care. It is seldom that a man holds the right bal-
ance between the two extremes. Those who strive and hope
and live only in the future, always looking ahead and impa-
tiently anticipating what is coming, as something which will
make them happy when they get it, are, in spite of their very
clever airs, exactly like those donkeys one sees in Italy, whose
pace may be hurried by fixing a stick on their heads with a
wisp of hay at the end of it; this is always just in front of
them, and they keep on trying to get it. Such people are in a
constant state of illusion as to their whole existence; they go
on living ad interim, until at last they die.
Instead, therefore, of always thinking about our plans and
anxiously looking to the future, or of giving ourselves up to
regret for the past, we should never forget that the present is
the only reality, the only certainty; that the future almost
always turns out contrary to our expectations; that the past,
too, was very different from what we suppose it to have been.
But the past and the future are, on the whole, of less conse-
quence than we think. Distance, which makes objects look
small to the outward eye, makes them look big to the eye of
thought. The present alone is true and actual; it is the only
time which possesses full reality, and our existence lies in it
17
Schopenhauer
exclusively. Therefore we should always be glad of it, and
give it the welcome it deserves, and enjoy every hour that is
bearable by its freedom from pain and annoyance with a full
consciousness of its value. We shall hardly be able to do this
if we make a wry face over the failure of our hopes in the past
or over our anxiety for the future. It is the height of folly to
refuse the present hour of happiness, or wantonly to spoil it
by vexation at by-gones or uneasiness about what is to come.
There is a time, of course, for forethought, nay, even for
repentance; but when it is over let us think of what is past as
of something to which we have said farewell, of necessity
subduing our hearts—
[Greek: alla ta men protuchthai easomen achnumenoi per
tumhon eni staethessi philon damasntes hanankae],
1
and of the future as of that which lies beyond our power, in
the lap of the gods—
[Greek: all aetoi men tauta theon en gounasi keitai.]
2
1 Iliad, xix, 65.]
2 Ibid, xvii, 514]
But in regard to the present let us remember Seneca’s advice,
and live each day as if it were our whole life,—singulas dies
singulas vitas puta: let us make it as agreeable as possible, it is
the only real time we have.
Only those evils which are sure to come at a definite date
have any right to disturb us; and how few there are which
fulfill this description. For evils are of two kinds; either they
are possible only, at most probable; or they are inevitable.
Even in the case of evils which are sure to happen, the time
at which they will happen is uncertain. A man who is always
preparing for either class of evil will not have a moment of
peace left him. So, if we are not to lose all comfort in life
through the fear of evils, some of which are uncertain in
themselves, and others, in the time at which they will occur,
we should look upon the one kind as never likely to happen,
and the other as not likely to happen very soon.
Now, the less our peace of mind is disturbed by fear, the
more likely it is to be agitated by desire and expectation.
This is the true meaning of that song of Goethe’s which is
such a favorite with everyone: Ich hab’ mein’ Sach’ auf nichts
gestellt. It is only after a man has got rid of all pretension,
18
Essays – Volume One
and taken refuge in mere unembellished existence, that he is
able to attain that peace of mind which is the foundation of
human happiness. Peace of mind! that is something essential
to any enjoyment of the present moment; and unless its sepa-
rate moments are enjoyed, there is an end of life’s happiness
as a whole. We should always collect that To-day comes only
once, and never returns. We fancy that it will come again to-
morrow; but To-morrow is another day, which, in its turn,
comes once only. We are apt to forget that every day is an
integral, and therefore irreplaceable portion of life, and to
look upon life as though it were a collective idea or name
which does not suffer if one of the individuals it covers is
destroyed.
We should be more likely to appreciate and enjoy the
present, if, in those good days when we are well and strong,
we did not fail to reflect how, in sickness and sorrow, every
past hour that was free from pain and privation seemed in
our memory so infinitely to be envied—as it were, a lost
paradise, or some one who was only then seen to have acted
as a friend. But we live through our days of happiness with-
out noticing them; it is only when evil comes upon us that
we wish them back. A thousand gay and pleasant hours are
wasted in ill-humor; we let them slip by unenjoyed, and sigh
for them in vain when the sky is overcast. Those present mo-
ments that are bearable, be they never so trite and common,—
passed by in indifference, or, it may be, impatiently pushed
away,—those are the moments we should honor; never failing
to remember that the ebbing tide is even how hurrying them
into the past, where memory will store them transfigured and
shining with an imperishable light,—in some after-time, and
above all, when our days are evil, to raise the veil and present
them as the object of our fondest regret.
SECTION 6. Limitations always make for happiness. We are
happy in proportion as our range of vision, our sphere of
work, our points of contact with the world, are restricted
and circumscribed. We are more likely to feel worried and
anxious if these limits are wide; for it means that our cares,
desires and terrors are increased and intensified. That is why
the blind are not so unhappy as we might be inclined to
suppose; otherwise there would not be that gentle and al-
most serene expression of peace in their faces.
19
Schopenhauer
Another reason why limitation makes for happiness is that
the second half of life proves even more dreary that the first.
As the years wear on, the horizon of our aims and our points
of contact with the world become more extended. In child-
hood our horizon is limited to the narrowest sphere about
us; in youth there is already a very considerable widening of
our view; in manhood it comprises the whole range of our
activity, often stretching out over a very distant sphere,—the
care, for instance, of a State or a nation; in old age it em-
braces posterity.
But even in the affairs of the intellect, limitation is neces-
sary if we are to be happy. For the less the will is excited, the
less we suffer. We have seen that suffering is something posi-
tive, and that happiness is only a negative condition. To limit
the sphere of outward activity is to relieve the will of external
stimulus: to limit the sphere of our intellectual efforts is to
relieve the will of internal sources of excitement. This latter
kind of limitation is attended by the disadvantage that it
opens the door to boredom, which is a direct source of count-
less sufferings; for to banish boredom, a man will have re-
course to any means that may be handy—dissipation, soci-
ety, extravagance, gaming, and drinking, and the like, which
in their turn bring mischief, ruin and misery in their train.
Difficiles in otio quies—it is difficult to keep quiet if you have
nothing to do. That limitation in the sphere of outward ac-
tivity is conducive, nay, even necessary to human happiness,
such as it is, may be seen in the fact that the only kind of
poetry which depicts men in a happy state of life—Idyllic
poetry, I mean,—always aims, as an intrinsic part of its treat-
ment, at representing them in very simple and restricted cir-
cumstances. It is this feeling, too, which is at the bottom of
the pleasure we take in what are called genre pictures.
Simplicity, therefore, as far as it can be attained, and even
monotony, in our manner of life, if it does not mean that we
are bored, will contribute to happiness; just because, under
such circumstances, life, and consequently the burden which
is the essential concomitant of life, will be least felt. Our
existence will glide on peacefully like a stream which no waves
or whirlpools disturb.
SECTION 7. Whether we are in a pleasant or a painful state
depends, ultimately, upon the kind of matter that pervades
20
Essays – Volume One
and engrosses our consciousness. In this respect, purely in-
tellectual occupation, for the mind that is capable of it, will,
as a rule, do much more in the way of happiness than any
form of practical life, with its constant alternations of success
and failure, and all the shocks and torments it produces. But it
must be confessed that for such occupation a pre-eminent
amount of intellectual capacity is necessary. And in this con-
nection it may be noted that, just as a life devoted to outward
activity will distract and divert a man from study, and also
deprive him of that quiet concentration of mind which is nec-
essary for such work; so, on the other hand, a long course of
thought will make him more or less unfit for the noisy pur-
suits of real life. It is advisable, therefore, to suspend mental
work for a while, if circumstances happen which demand any
degree of energy in affairs of a practical nature.
SECTION 8. To live a life that shall be entirely prudent and
discreet, and to draw from experience all the instruction it
contains, it is requisite to be constantly thinking back,—to
make a kind of recapitulation of what we have done, of our
impressions and sensations, to compare our former with our
present judgments—what we set before us and struggle to
achieve, with the actual result and satisfaction we have ob-
tained. To do this is to get a repetition of the private lessons
of experience,—lessons which are given to every one.
Experience of the world may be looked upon as a kind of
text, to which reflection and knowledge form the commen-
tary. Where there is great deal of reflection and intellectual
knowledge, and very little experience, the result is like those
books which have on each page two lines of text to forty
lines of commentary. A great deal of experience with little
reflection and scant knowledge, gives us books like those of
the editio Bipontina
1
where there are no notes and much
that is unintelligible.
The advice here given is on a par with a rule recommended
by Pythagoras,—to review, every night before going to sleep,
what we have done during the day. To live at random, in the
hurly-burly of business or pleasure, without ever reflecting
1 Translator’s Note. A series of Greek, Latin and French clas-
sics published at Zweibräcken in the Palatinate, from and
after the year 1779. Cf. Butter, Ueber die Bipontiner und die
editiones Bipontinae.
21
Schopenhauer
upon the past,—to go on, as it were, pulling cotton off the
reel of life,—is to have no clear idea of what we are about;
and a man who lives in this state will have chaos in his emo-
tions and certain confusion in his thoughts; as is soon mani-
fest by the abrupt and fragmentary character of his conver-
sation, which becomes a kind of mincemeat. A man will be
all the more exposed to this fate in proportion as he lives a
restless life in the world, amid a crowd of various impres-
sions and with a correspondingly small amount of activity
on the part of his own mind.
And in this connection it will be in place to observe that,
when events and circumstances which have influenced us
pass away in the course of time, we are unable to bring back
and renew the particular mood or state of feeling which they
aroused in us: but we can remember what we were led to say
and do in regard to them; and thus form, as it were, the
result, expression and measure of those events. We should,
therefore, be careful to preserve the memory of our thoughts
at important points in our life; and herein lies the great ad-
vantage of keeping a journal.
SECTION 9. To be self-sufficient, to be all in all to oneself,
to want for nothing, to be able to say omnia mea mecum
porto—that is assuredly the chief qualification for happiness.
Hence Aristotle’s remark, [Greek: hae eudaimonia ton
autarchon esti]
1
—to be happy means to be self-sufficient—
cannot be too often repeated. It is, at bottom, the same
thought as is present in the very well-turned sentence from
Chamfort:
Le bonheur n’est pas chose aisée: il est très difficile de le trouver
en nous, et impossible de le trouver ailleurs.
For while a man cannot reckon with certainty upon any-
one but himself, the burdens and disadvantages, the dangers
and annoyances, which arise from having to do with others,
are not only countless but unavoidable.
There is no more mistaken path to happiness than world-
liness, revelry, high life: for the whole object of it is to trans-
form our miserable existence into a succession of joys, de-
lights and pleasures,—a process which cannot fail to result
1 Eudem. Eth. VII. ii. 37.
22
Essays – Volume One
in disappointment and delusion; on a par, in this respect,
with its obligato accompaniment, the interchange of lies.
1
All society necessarily involves, as the first condition of its
existence, mutual accommodation and restraint upon the part
of its members. This means that the larger it is, the more
insipid will be its tone. A man can be himself only so long as
he is alone; and if he does not love solitude, he will not love
freedom; for it is only when he is alone that he is really free.
Constraint is always present in society, like a companion of
whom there is no riddance; and in proportion to the great-
ness of a man’s individuality, it will be hard for him to bear
the sacrifices which all intercourse with others demands, Soli-
tude will be welcomed or endured or avoided, according as a
man’s personal value is large or small,—the wretch feeling,
when he is alone, the whole burden of his misery; the great
intellect delighting in its greatness; and everyone, in short,
being just what he is.
Further, if a man stands high in Nature’s lists, it is natural
and inevitable that he should feel solitary. It will be an ad-
vantage to him if his surroundings do not interfere with this
feeling; for if he has to see a great deal of other people who
are not of like character with himself, they will exercise a
disturbing influence upon him, adverse to his peace of mind;
they will rob him, in fact, of himself, and give him nothing
to compensate for the loss.
But while Nature sets very wide differences between man
and man in respect both of morality and of intellect, society
disregards and effaces them; or, rather, it sets up artificial
differences in their stead,—gradations of rank and position,
which are very often diametrically opposed to those which
Nature establishes. The result of this arrangement is to el-
evate those whom Nature has placed low, and to depress the
few who stand high. These latter, then, usually withdraw
from society, where, as soon as it is at all numerous, vulgarity
reigns supreme.
What offends a great intellect in society is the equality of
rights, leading to equality of pretensions, which everyone
enjoys; while at the same time, inequality of capacity means
1 As our body is concealed by the clothes we wear, so our
mind is veiled in lies. The veil is always there, and it is only
through it that we can sometimes guess at what a man really
thinks; just as from his clothes we arrive at the general shape
of his body.
23
Schopenhauer
a corresponding disparity of social power. So-called good so-
ciety recognizes every kind of claim but that of intellect, which
is a contraband article; and people are expected to exhibit an
unlimited amount of patience towards every form of folly
and stupidity, perversity and dullness; whilst personal merit
has to beg pardon, as it were, for being present, or else con-
ceal itself altogether. Intellectual superiority offends by its
very existence, without any desire to do so.
The worst of what is called good society is not only that it
offers us the companionship of people who are unable to
win either our praise or our affection, but that it does not
allow of our being that which we naturally are; it compels
us, for the sake of harmony, to shrivel up, or even alter our
shape altogether. Intellectual conversation, whether grave or
humorous, is only fit for intellectual society; it is downright
abhorrent to ordinary people, to please whom it is absolutely
necessary to be commonplace and dull. This demands an act
of severe self-denial; we have to forfeit three-fourths of our-
selves in order to become like other people. No doubt their
company may be set down against our loss in this respect;
but the more a man is worth, the more he will find that what
he gains does not cover what he loses, and that the balance is
on the debit side of the account; for the people with whom
he deals are generally bankrupt,—that is to say, there is noth-
ing to be got from their society which can compensate either
for its boredom, annoyance and disagreeableness, or for the
self-denial which it renders necessary. Accordingly, most so-
ciety is so constituted as to offer a good profit to anyone
who will exchange it for solitude.
Nor is this all. By way of providing a substitute for real—
I mean intellectual—superiority, which is seldom to be met
with, and intolerable when it is found, society has capriciously
adopted a false kind of superiority, conventional in its char-
acter, and resting upon arbitrary principles,—a tradition, as
it were, handed down in the higher circles, and, like a pass-
word, subject to alteration; I refer to bon-ton fashion. When-
ever this kind of superiority comes into collision with the
real kind, its weakness is manifest. Moreover, the presence of
good tone means the absence of good sense.
No man can be in perfect accord with any one but him-
self—not even with a friend or the partner of his life; differ-
ences of individuality and temperament are always bringing
24
Essays – Volume One
in some degree of discord, though it may be a very slight
one. That genuine, profound peace of mind, that perfect
tranquillity of soul, which, next to health, is the highest bless-
ing the earth can give, is to be attained only in solitude, and,
as a permanent mood, only in complete retirement; and then,
if there is anything great and rich in the man’s own self, his
way of life is the happiest that may be found in this wretched
world.
Let me speak plainly. However close the bond of friend-
ship, love, marriage—a man, ultimately, looks to himself, to
his own welfare alone; at most, to his child’s too. The less
necessity there is for you to come into contact with mankind
in general, in the relations whether of business or of personal
intimacy, the better off you are. Loneliness and solitude have
their evils, it is true; but if you cannot feel them all at once,
you can at least see where they lie; on the other hand, society
is insidious in this respect; as in offering you what appears to
be the pastime of pleasing social intercourse, it works great
and often irreparable mischief. The young should early be
trained to bear being left alone; for it is a source of happiness
and peace of mind.
It follows from this that a man is best off if he be thrown
upon his own resources and can be all in all to himself; and
Cicero goes so far as to say that a man who is in this condition
cannot fail to be very happy—nemo potest non beatissimus esse
qui est totus aptus ex sese, quique in se uno ponit omnia.
1
The
more a man has in himself, the less others can be to him. The
feeling of self-sufficiency! it is that which restrains those whose
personal value is in itself great riches, from such considerable
sacrifices as are demanded by intercourse with the world, let
alone, then, from actually practicing self-denial by going out
of their way to seek it. Ordinary people are sociable and com-
plaisant just from the very opposite feeling;—to bear others’
company is easier for them than to bear their own. Moreover,
respect is not paid in this world to that which has real merit; it
is reserved for that which has none. So retirement is at once a
proof and a result of being distinguished by the possession of
meritorious qualities. It will therefore show real wisdom on
the part of any one who is worth anything in himself, to limit
his requirements as may be necessary, in order to preserve or
extend his freedom, and,—since a man must come into some
1 Paradoxa Stoidorum: II.
25
Schopenhauer
relations with his fellow-men—to admit them to his intimacy
as little as possible.
I have said that people are rendered sociable by their abil-
ity to endure solitude, that is to say, their own society. They
become sick of themselves. It is this vacuity of soul which
drives them to intercourse with others,—to travels in for-
eign countries. Their mind is wanting in elasticity; it has no
movement of its own, and so they try to give it some,—by
drink, for instance. How much drunkenness is due to this
cause alone! They are always looking for some form of ex-
citement, of the strongest kind they can bear—the excite-
ment of being with people of like nature with themselves;
and if they fail in this, their mind sinks by its own weight,
and they fall into a grievous lethargy.
1
Such people, it may
be said, possess only a small fraction of humanity in them-
selves; and it requires a great many of them put together to
make up a fair amount of it,—to attain any degree of con-
sciousness as men. A man, in the full sense of the word,—a
man par excellence—does not represent a fraction, but a whole
number: he is complete in himself.
Ordinary society is, in this respect, very like the kind of
music to be obtained from an orchestra composed of Rus-
sian horns. Each horn has only one note; and the music is
produced by each note coming in just at the right moment.
In the monotonous sound of a single horn, you have a pre-
cise illustration of the effect of most people’s minds. How
1 It is a well-known fact, that we can more easily bear up
under evils which fall upon a great many people besides our-
selves. As boredom seems to be an evil of this kind, people
band together to offer it a common resistance. The love of
life is at bottom only the fear of death; and, in the same way,
the social impulse does not rest directly upon the love of
society, but upon the fear of solitude; it is not alone the charm
of being in others’ company that people seek, it is the dreary
oppression of being alone—the monotony of their own con-
sciousness—that they would avoid. They will do anything
to escape it,—even tolerate bad companions, and put up with
the feeling of constraint which all society involves, in this
case a very burdensome one. But if aversion to such society
conquers the aversion to being alone, they become accus-
tomed to solitude and hardened to its immediate effects. They
no longer find solitude to be such a very bad thing, and
settle down comfortably to it without any hankering after
society;—and this, partly because it is only indirectly that
they need others’ company, and partly because they have be-
come accustomed to the benefits of being alone.
26
Essays – Volume One
often there seems to be only one thought there! and no room
for any other. It is easy to see why people are so bored; and
also why they are sociable, why they like to go about in
crowds—why mankind is so gregarious. It is the monotony
of his own nature that makes a man find solitude intoler-
able. Omnis stultitia laborat fastidio sui: folly is truly its own
burden. Put a great many men together, and you may get
some result—some music from your horns!
A man of intellect is like an artist who gives a concert with-
out any help from anyone else, playing on a single instru-
ment—a piano, say, which is a little orchestra in itself. Such
a man is a little world in himself; and the effect produced by
various instruments together, he produces single-handed, in
the unity of his own consciousness. Like the piano, he has
no place in a symphony: he is a soloist and performs by him-
self,—in solitude, it may be; or, if in company with other
instruments, only as principal; or for setting the tone, as in
singing. However, those who are fond of society from time
to time may profit by this simile, and lay it down as a general
rule that deficiency of quality in those we meet may be to
some extent compensated by an increase in quantity. One
man’s company may be quite enough, if he is clever; but
where you have only ordinary people to deal with, it is advis-
able to have a great many of them, so that some advantage
may accrue by letting them all work together,—on the anal-
ogy of the horns; and may Heaven grant you patience for
your task!
That mental vacuity and barrenness of soul to which I have
alluded, is responsible for another misfortune. When men of
the better class form a society for promoting some noble or
ideal aim, the result almost always is that the innumerable
mob of humanity comes crowding in too, as it always does
everywhere, like vermin—their object being to try and get rid
of boredom, or some other defect of their nature; and any-
thing that will effect that, they seize upon at once, without the
slightest discrimination. Some of them will slip into that soci-
ety, or push themselves in, and then either soon destroy it
altogether, or alter it so much that in the end it comes to have
a purpose the exact opposite of that which it had at first.
This is not the only point of view from which the social
impulse may be regarded. On cold days people manage to
get some warmth by crowding together; and you can warm
27
Schopenhauer
your mind in the same way—by bringing it into contact
with others. But a man who has a great deal of intellectual
warmth in himself will stand in no need of such resources. I
have written a little fable illustrating this: it may be found
elsewhere.
1
As a general rule, it may be said that a man’s
sociability stands very nearly in inverse ratio to his intellec-
tual value: to say that “so and so” is very unsociable, is al-
most tantamount to saying that he is a man of great capacity.
Solitude is doubly advantageous to such a man. Firstly, it
allows him to be with himself, and, secondly, it prevents him
being with others—an advantage of great moment; for how
much constraint, annoyance, and even danger there is in all
intercourse with the world. Tout notre mal, says La Bruyère,
vient de ne pouvoir être seul. It is really a very risky, nay, a fatal
thing, to be sociable; because it means contact with natures,
the great majority of which are bad morally, and dull or per-
verse, intellectually. To be unsociable is not to care about
such people; and to have enough in oneself to dispense with
the necessity of their company is a great piece of good for-
tune; because almost all our sufferings spring from having to
do with other people; and that destroys the peace of mind,
which, as I have said, comes next after health in the elements
of happiness. Peace of mind is impossible without a consid-
erable amount of solitude. The Cynics renounced all private
property in order to attain the bliss of having nothing to
trouble them; and to renounce society with the same object
1: Translator’s Note. The passage to which Schopenhauer re-
fers is Parerga: vol. ii. § 413 (4th edition). The fable is of
certain porcupines, who huddled together for warmth on a
cold day; but as they began to prick one another with their
quills, they were obliged to disperse. However the cold drove
them together again, when just the same thing happened. At
last, after many turns of huddling and dispersing, they dis-
covered that they would be best off by remaining at a little
distance from one another. In the same way, the need of
society drives the human porcupines together—only to be
mutually repelled by the many prickly and disagreeable quali-
ties of their nature. The moderate distance which they at last
discover to be the only tolerable condition of intercourse, is
the code of politeness and fine manners; and those who trans-
gress it are roughly told—in the English phrase—to keep their
distance. By this arrangement the mutual need of warmth is
only very moderately satisfied,—but then people do not get
pricked. A man who has some heat in himself prefers to re-
main outside, where he will neither prick other people nor
get pricked himself.
28
Essays – Volume One
is the wisest thing a man can do. Bernardin de Saint Pierre
has the very excellent and pertinent remark that to be spar-
ing in regard to food is a means of health; in regard to soci-
ety, a means of tranquillity—la diète des ailmens nous rend la
santé du corps, et celle des hommes la tranquillité de l’âme. To
be soon on friendly, or even affectionate, terms with solitude
is like winning a gold mine; but this is not something which
everybody can do. The prime reason for social intercourse is
mutual need; and as soon as that is satisfied, boredom drives
people together once more. If it were not for these two rea-
sons, a man would probably elect to remain alone; if only
because solitude is the sole condition of life which gives full
play to that feeling of exclusive importance which every man
has in his own eyes,—as if he were the only person in the
world! a feeling which, in the throng and press of real life,
soon shrivels up to nothing, getting, at every step, a painful
démenti. From this point of view it may be said that solitude
is the original and natural state of man, where, like another
Adam, he is as happy as his nature will allow.
But still, had Adam no father or mother? There is another
sense in which solitude is not the natural state; for, at his
entrance into the world, a man finds himself with parents,
brothers, sisters, that is to say, in society, and not alone. Ac-
cordingly it cannot be said that the love of solitude is an
original characteristic of human nature; it is rather the result
of experience and reflection, and these in their turn depend
upon the development of intellectual power, and increase
with the years.
Speaking generally, sociability stands in inverse ratio with
age. A little child raises a piteous cry of fright if it is left alone
for only a few minutes; and later on, to be shut up by itself is
a great punishment. Young people soon get on very friendly
terms with one another; it is only the few among them of
any nobility of mind who are glad now and then to be
alone;—but to spend the whole day thus would be disagree-
able. A grown-up man can easily do it; it is little trouble to
him to be much alone, and it becomes less and less trouble
as he advances in years. An old man who has outlived all his
friends, and is either indifferent or dead to the pleasures of
life, is in his proper element in solitude; and in individual
cases the special tendency to retirement and seclusion will
always be in direct proportion to intellectual capacity.
29
Schopenhauer
For this tendency is not, as I have said, a purely natural
one; it does not come into existence as a direct need of hu-
man nature; it is rather the effect of the experience we go
through, the product of reflection upon what our needs re-
ally are; proceeding, more especially, from the insight we at-
tain into the wretched stuff of which most people are made,
whether you look at their morals or their intellects. The worst
of it all is that, in the individual, moral and intellectual short-
comings are closely connected and play into each other’s
hands, so that all manner of disagreeable results are obtained,
which make intercourse with most people not only unpleas-
ant but intolerable. Hence, though the world contains many
things which are thoroughly bad, the worst thing in it is
society. Even Voltaire, that sociable Frenchman, was obliged
to admit that there are everywhere crowds of people not worth
talking to: la terre est couverte de gens qui ne méritent pas qu’on
leur parle. And Petrarch gives a similar reason for wishing to
be alone—that tender spirit! so strong and constant in his
love of seclusion. The streams, the plains and woods know
well, he says, how he has tried to escape the perverse and
stupid people who have missed the way to heaven:—
Cercato ho sempre solitaria vita
(Le rive il sanno, e le campagne e i boschi)
Per fuggir quest’ ingegni storti e loschi
Che la strada del ciel’ hanno smarrita.
He pursues the same strain in that delightful book of his,
DeVita Solitaria, which seems to have given Zimmerman
the idea of his celebrated work on Solitude. It is the second-
ary and indirect character of the love of seclusion to which
Chamfort alludes in the following passage, couched in his
sarcastic vein: On dit quelquefois d’un homme qui vit seul, il
n’aime pas la société. C’est souvent comme si on disait d’un
homme qu’il n’aime pas la promenade, sous le pretexte qu’il ne
se promène pas volontiers le soir dans le forêt de Bondy.
You will find a similar sentiment expressed by the Persian
poet Sadi, in his Garden of Roses. Since that time, he says, we
have taken leave of society, preferring the path of seclusion; for
there is safety in solitude. Angelus Silesius,
1
a very gentle and
1 Translator’s Note. Angelus Silesius, pseudonym for Johannes
Scheffler, a physician and mystic poet of the seventeenth
century (1624-77).
30
Essays – Volume One
Christian writer, confesses to the same feeling, in his own
mythical language. Herod, he says, is the common enemy;
and when, as with Joseph, God warns us of danger, we fly
from the world to solitude, from Bethlehem to Egypt; or
else suffering and death await us!—
Herodes ist ein Feind; der Joseph der Verstand,
Dem machte Gott die Gefahr im Traum (in Geist) bekannt;
Die Welt ist Bethlehem, Aegypten Einsamkeit,
Fleuch, meine Seele! fleuch, sonst stirbest du vor Leid.
Giordano Bruno also declares himself a friend of seclu-
sion. Tanti uomini, he says, che in terra hanno voluto gustare
vita celeste, dissero con una voce, “ecce elongavi fugiens et mansi
in solitudine”—those who in this world have desired a fore-
taste of the divine life, have always proclaimed with one voice:
Lo! then would I wander far off;
I would lodge in the wilderness.
1
1 Psalms, lv. 7.
And in the work from which I have already quoted, Sadi
says of himself: In disgust with my friends at Damascus, I with-
drew into the desert about Jerusalem, to seek the society of the
beasts of the field. In short, the same thing has been said by all
whom Prometheus has formed out of better clay. What plea-
sure could they find in the company of people with whom
their only common ground is just what is lowest and least
noble in their own nature—the part of them that is com-
monplace, trivial and vulgar? What do they want with people
who cannot rise to a higher level, and for whom nothing
remains but to drag others down to theirs? for this is what
they aim at. It is an aristocratic feeling that is at the bottom
of this propensity to seclusion and solitude.
Rascals are always sociable—more’s the pity! and the chief
sign that a man has any nobility in his character is the little
pleasure he takes in others’ company. He prefers solitude more
and more, and, in course of time, comes to see that, with few
exceptions, the world offers no choice beyond solitude on
one side and vulgarity on the other. This may sound a hard
thing to say; but even Angelus Silesius, with all his Christian
feelings of gentleness and love, was obliged to admit the truth
31
Schopenhauer
of it. However painful solitude may be, he says, be careful
not to be vulgar; for then you may find a desert everywhere:—
Die Einsamkeit ist noth: doch sei nur nicht gemein,
So kannst du überall in einer Wüste sein.
It is natural for great minds—the true teachers of humanity—
to care little about the constant company of others; just as
little as the schoolmaster cares for joining in the gambols of
the noisy crowd of boys which surround him. The mission of
these great minds is to guide mankind over the sea of error to
the haven of truth—to draw it forth from the dark abysses of
a barbarous vulgarity up into the light of culture and refine-
ment. Men of great intellect live in the world without really
belonging to it; and so, from their earliest years, they feel that
there is a perceptible difference between them and other people.
But it is only gradually, with the lapse of years, that they come
to a clear understanding of their position. Their intellectual
isolation is then reinforced by actual seclusion in their man-
ner of life; they let no one approach who is not in some degree
emancipated from the prevailing vulgarity.
From what has been said it is obvious that the love of soli-
tude is not a direct, original impulse in human nature, but
rather something secondary and of gradual growth. It is the
more distinguishing feature of nobler minds, developed not
without some conquest of natural desires, and now and then
in actual opposition to the promptings of Mephistopheles—
bidding you exchange a morose and soul-destroying solitude
for life amongst men, for society; even the worst, he says,
will give a sense of human fellowship:—
Hör’ auf mit deinem Gram zu spielen,
Der, wie ein Geier, dir am Leben frisst:
Die schlechteste Gesellschaft lässt dich fühlen
Dass du ein Mensch mit Menschen bist.
1
To be alone is the fate of all great minds—a fate deplored at
times, but still always chosen as the less grievous of two evils.
As the years increase, it always becomes easier to say, Dare to
be wise—sapere aude. And after sixty, the inclination to be
alone grows into a kind of real, natural instinct; for at that
1 Goethe’s Faust, Part I., 1281-5.
32
Essays – Volume One
age everything combines in favor of it. The strongest im-
pulse—the love of woman’s society—has little or no effect;
it is the sexless condition of old age which lays the founda-
tion of a certain self-sufficiency, and that gradually absorbs
all desire for others’ company. A thousand illusions and fol-
lies are overcome; the active years of life are in most cases
gone; a man has no more expectations or plans or inten-
tions. The generation to which he belonged has passed away,
and a new race has sprung up which looks upon him as es-
sentially outside its sphere of activity. And then the years
pass more quickly as we become older, and we want to de-
vote our remaining time to the intellectual rather than to the
practical side of life. For, provided that the mind retains its
faculties, the amount of knowledge and experience we have
acquired, together with the facility we have gained in the use
of our powers, makes it then more than ever easy and inter-
esting to us to pursue the study of any subject. A thousand
things become clear which were formerly enveloped in ob-
scurity, and results are obtained which give a feeling of diffi-
culties overcome. From long experience of men, we cease to
expect much from them; we find that, on the whole, people
do not gain by a nearer acquaintance; and that—apart from
a few rare and fortunate exceptions—we have come across
none but defective specimens of human nature which it is
advisable to leave in peace. We are no more subject to the
ordinary illusions of life; and as, in individual instances, we
soon see what a man is made of, we seldom feel any inclina-
tion to come into closer relations with him. Finally, isola-
tion—our own society—has become a habit, as it were a
second nature to us, more especially if we have been on
friendly terms with it from our youth up. The love of soli-
tude which was formerly indulged only at the expense of our
desire for society, has now come to be the simple quality of
our natural disposition—the element proper to our life, as
water to a fish. This is why anyone who possesses a unique
individuality—unlike others and therefore necessarily iso-
lated—feels that, as he becomes older, his position is no longer
so burdensome as when he was young.
For, as a matter of fact, this very genuine privilege of old
age is one which can be enjoyed only if a man is possessed of
a certain amount of intellect; it will be appreciated most of
all where there is real mental power; but in some degree by
33
Schopenhauer
every one. It is only people of very barren and vulgar nature
who will be just as sociable in their old age as they were in
their youth. But then they become troublesome to a society
to which they are no longer suited, and, at most, manage to
be tolerated; whereas, they were formerly in great request.
There is another aspect of this inverse proportion between
age and sociability—the way in which it conduces to educa-
tion. The younger that people are, the more in every respect
they have to learn; and it is just in youth that Nature pro-
vides a system of mutual education, so that mere intercourse
with others, at that time of life, carries instruction with it.
Human society, from this point of view, resembles a huge
academy of learning, on the Bell and Lancaster system, op-
posed to the system of education by means of books and
schools, as something artificial and contrary to the institu-
tions of Nature. It is therefore a very suitable arrangement
that, in his young days, a man should be a very diligent stu-
dent at the place of learning provided by Nature herself.
But there is nothing in life which has not some drawback—
nihil est ab omni parte beatum, as Horace says; or, in the
words of an Indian proverb, no lotus without a stalk. Seclu-
sion, which has so many advantages, has also its little annoy-
ances and drawbacks, which are small, however, in compari-
son with those of society; hence anyone who is worth much
in himself will get on better without other people than with
them. But amongst the disadvantages of seclusion there is
one which is not so easy to see as the rest. It is this: when
people remain indoors all day, they become physically very
sensitive to atmospheric changes, so that every little draught
is enough to make them ill; so with our temper; a long course
of seclusion makes it so sensitive that the most trivial inci-
dents, words, or even looks, are sufficient to disturb or to
vex and offend us—little things which are unnoticed by those
who live in the turmoil of life.
When you find human society disagreeable and feel your-
self justified in flying to solitude, you can be so constituted
as to be unable to bear the depression of it for any length of
time, which will probably be the case if you are young. Let
me advise you, then, to form the habit of taking some of
your solitude with you into society, to learn to be to some
extent alone even though you are in company; not to say at
once what you think, and, on the other hand, not to attach
34
Essays – Volume One
too precise a meaning to what others say; rather, not to ex-
pect much of them, either morally or intellectually, and to
strengthen yourself in the feeling of indifference to their
opinion, which is the surest way of always practicing a praise-
worthy toleration. If you do that, you will not live so much
with other people, though you may appear to move amongst
them: your relation to them will be of a purely objective
character. This precaution will keep you from too close con-
tact with society, and therefore secure you against being con-
taminated or even outraged by it.
1
Society is in this respect
like a fire—the wise man warming himself at a proper dis-
tance from it; not coming too close, like the fool, who, on
getting scorched, runs away and shivers in solitude, loud in
his complaint that the fire burns.
1 This restricted, or, as it were, entrenched kind of sociabil-
ity has been dramatically illustrated in a play—well worth
reading—of Moratin’s, entitled El Café o sea la Comedia
Nuova (The Cafe or the New Comedy), chiefly by one of
the characters, Don Pedro and especially in the second and
third scenes of the first act.
SECTION 10. Envy is natural to man; and still, it is at once
a vice and a source of misery.
1
We should treat it as the en-
emy of our happiness, and stifle it like an evil thought. This
is the advice given by Seneca; as he well puts it, we shall be
pleased with what we have, if we avoid the self-torture of
comparing our own lot with some other and happier one—
nostra nos sine comparatione delectent; nunquam erit felix quem
torquebit felicior.
2
And again, quum adspexeris quot te ante-
cedent, cogita quot sequantur
3
—if a great many people ap-
pear to be better off than yourself, think how many there are
in a worse position. It is a fact that if real calamity comes
upon us, the most effective consolation—though it springs
from the same source as envy—is just the thought of greater
misfortunes than ours; and the next best is the society of
those who are in the same luck as we—the partners of our
sorrows.
1 Envy shows how unhappy people are; and their constant
attention to what others do and leave undone, how much
they are bored.
2: De Ira: iii., 30.
3 Epist. xv.
35
Schopenhauer
So much for the envy which we may feel towards others.
As regards the envy which we may excite in them, it should
always be remembered that no form of hatred is so impla-
cable as the hatred that comes from envy; and therefore we
should always carefully refrain from doing anything to rouse
it; nay, as with many another form of vice, it is better alto-
gether to renounce any pleasure there may be in it, because
of the serious nature of its consequences.
Aristocracies are of three kinds: (1) of birth and rank; (2)
of wealth; and (3) of intellect. The last is really the most
distinguished of the three, and its claim to occupy the first
position comes to be recognized, if it is only allowed time to
work. So eminent a king as Frederick the Great admitted
it—_les âmes privilegiées rangent à l’égal des souverains_, as
he said to his chamberlain, when the latter expressed his sur-
prise that Voltaire should have a seat at the table reserved for
kings and princes, whilst ministers and generals were rel-
egated to the chamberlain’s.
Every one of these aristocracies is surrounded by a host of
envious persons. If you belong to one of them, they will be
secretly embittered against you; and unless they are restrained
by fear, they will always be anxious to let you understand
that you are no better than they. It is by their anxiety to let you
know this, that they betray how greatly they are conscious
that the opposite is the truth.
The line of conduct to be pursued if you are exposed to
envy, is to keep the envious persons at a distance, and, as far
as possible, avoid all contact with them, so that there may be
a wide gulf fixed between you and them; if this cannot be
done, to bear their attacks with the greatest composure. In
the latter case, the very thing that provokes the attack will
also neutralize it. This is what appears to be generally done.
The members of one of these aristocracies usually get on
very well with those of another, and there is no call for envy
between them, because their several privileges effect an equi-
poise.
36
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 11. Give mature and repeated consideration to
any plan before you proceed to carry it out; and even after
you have thoroughly turned it over in your mind, make some
concession to the incompetency of human judgment; for it
may always happen that circumstances which cannot be in-
vestigated or foreseen, will come in and upset the whole of
your calculation. This is a reflection that will always influ-
ence the negative side of the balance—a kind of warning to
refrain from unnecessary action in matters of importance—
quieta non movere. But having once made up your mind and
begun your work, you must let it run its course and abide
the result—not worry yourself by fresh reflections on what
is already accomplished, or by a renewal of your scruples on
the score of possible danger: free your mind from the subject
altogether, and refuse to go into it again, secure in the thought
that you gave it mature attention at the proper time. This is
the same advice as is given by an Italian proverb—legala bene
e poi lascia la andare—which Goethe has translated thus:
See well to your girths, and then ride on boldly.
1
1 It may be observed, in passing, that a great many of the
maxims which Goethe puts under the head of Proverbial, are
translations from the Italian.
And if, notwithstanding that, you fail, it is because human
affairs are the sport of chance and error. Socrates, the wisest
of men, needed the warning voice of his good genius, or
[Greek: daimonion], to enable him to do what was right in
regard to his own personal affairs, or at any rate, to avoid
mistakes; which argues that the human intellect is incompe-
tent for the purpose. There is a saying—which is reported to
have originated with one of the Popes—that when misfor-
tune happens to us, the blame of it, at least in some degree,
attaches to ourselves. If this is not true absolutely and in
every instance, it is certainly true in the great majority of
cases. It even looks as if this truth had a great deal to do with
the effort people make as far as possible to conceal their mis-
fortunes, and to put the best face they can upon them, for
fear lest their misfortunes may show how much they are to
blame.
37
Schopenhauer
SECTION 12. In the case of a misfortune which has al-
ready happened and therefore cannot be altered, you should
not allow yourself to think that it might have been other-
wise; still less, that it might have been avoided by such and
such means; for reflections of this kind will only add to your
distress and make it intolerable, so that you will become a
tormentor to yourself—[Greek: heautontimoroumeaeos]. It
is better to follow the example of King David; who, as long
as his son lay on the bed of sickness, assailed Jehovah with
unceasing supplications and entreaties for his recovery; but
when he was dead, snapped his fingers and thought no more
of it. If you are not light-hearted enough for that, you can
take refuge in fatalism, and have the great truth revealed to
you that everything which happens is the result of necessity,
and therefore inevitable.
However good this advice may be, it is one-sided and par-
tial. In relieving and quieting us for the moment, it is no
doubt effective enough; but when our misfortunes have re-
sulted—as is usually the case—from our own carelessness or
folly, or, at any rate, partly by our own fault, it is a good
thing to consider how they might have been avoided, and to
consider it often in spite of its being a tender subject—a
salutary form of self-discipline, which will make us wiser and
better men for the future. If we have made obvious mistakes,
we should not try, as we generally do, to gloss them over, or
to find something to excuse or extenuate them; we should
admit to ourselves that we have committed faults, and open
our eyes wide to all their enormity, in order that we may
firmly resolve to avoid them in time to come. To be sure,
that means a great deal of self-inflicted pain, in the shape of
discontent, but it should be remembered that to spare the
rod is to spoil the child—[Greek: ho mae dareis anthropos
ou paideuetai].
1
1 Menander. Monost: 422.
38
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 13. In all matters affecting our weal or woe, we
should be careful not to let our imagination run away with
us, and build no castles in the air. In the first place, they are
expensive to build, because we have to pull them down again
immediately, and that is a source of grief. We should be still
more on our guard against distressing our hearts by depict-
ing possible misfortunes. If these were misfortunes of a purely
imaginary kind, or very remote and unlikely, we should at
once see, on awaking from our dream, that the whole thing
was mere illusion; we should rejoice all the more in a reality
better than our dreams, or at most, be warned against mis-
fortunes which, though very remote, were still possible. These,
however, are not the sort of playthings in which imagination
delights; it is only in idle hours that we build castles in the
air, and they are always of a pleasing description. The matter
which goes to form gloomy dreams are mischances which to
some extent really threaten us, though it be from some dis-
tance; imagination makes us look larger and nearer and more
terrible than they are in reality. This is a kind of dream which
cannot be so readily shaken off on awaking as a pleasant
one; for a pleasant dream is soon dispelled by reality, leav-
ing, at most, a feeble hope lying in the lap of possibility.
Once we have abandoned ourselves to a fit of the blues, vi-
sions are conjured up which do not so easily vanish again;
for it is always just possible that the visions may be realized.
But we are not always able to estimate the exact degree of
possibility: possibility may easily pass into probability; and
thus we deliver ourselves up to torture. Therefore we should
be careful not to be over-anxious on any matter affecting our
weal or our woe, not to carry our anxiety to unreasonable or
injudicious limits; but coolly and dispassionately to deliber-
ate upon the matter, as though it were an abstract question
which did not touch us in particular. We should give no play
to imagination here; for imagination is not judgment—it
only conjures up visions, inducing an unprofitable and of-
ten very painful mood.
The rule on which I am here insisting should be most care-
fully observed towards evening. For as darkness makes us
timid and apt to see terrifying shapes everywhere, there is
something similar in the effect of indistinct thought; and
uncertainty always brings with it a sense of danger. Hence,
towards evening, when our powers of thought and judgment
39
Schopenhauer
are relaxed,—at the hour, as it were, of subjective darkness,—
the intellect becomes tired, easily confused, and unable to
get at the bottom of things; and if, in that state, we meditate
on matters of personal interest to ourselves, they soon as-
sume a dangerous and terrifying aspect. This is mostly the
case at night, when we are in bed; for then the mind is fully
relaxed, and the power of judgment quite unequal to its du-
ties; but imagination is still awake. Night gives a black look
to everything, whatever it may be. This is why our thoughts,
just before we go to sleep, or as we lie awake through the
hours of the night, are usually such confusions and perver-
sions of facts as dreams themselves; and when our thoughts
at that time are concentrated upon our own concerns, they
are generally as black and monstrous as possible. In the morn-
ing all such nightmares vanish like dreams: as the Spanish
proverb has it, noche tinta, bianco el dia—the night is col-
ored, the day is white. But even towards nightfall, as soon as
the candles are lit, the mind, like the eye, no longer sees
things so clearly as by day: it is a time unsuited to serious
meditation, especially on unpleasant subjects. The morning
is the proper time for that—as indeed for all efforts without
exception, whether mental or bodily. For the morning is the
youth of the day, when everything is bright, fresh, and easy
of attainment; we feel strong then, and all our faculties are
completely at our disposal. Do not shorten the morning by
getting up late, or waste it in unworthy occupations or in
talk; look upon it as the quintessence of life, as to a certain
extent sacred. Evening is like old age: we are languid, talk-
ative, silly. Each day is a little life: every waking and rising a
little birth, every fresh morning a little youth, every going to
rest and sleep a little death.
But condition of health, sleep, nourishment, temperature,
weather, surroundings, and much else that is purely exter-
nal, have, in general, an important influence upon our mood
and therefore upon our thoughts. Hence both our view of
any matter and our capacity for any work are very much
subject to time and place. So it is best to profit by a good
mood—for how seldom it comes!—
Nehmt die gute Stimmung wahr,
Denn sie kommt so selten.
1
1 Goethe.
40
Essays – Volume One
We are not always able to form new ideas about; our sur-
roundings, or to command original thoughts: they come if
they will, and when they will. And so, too, we cannot always
succeed in completely considering some personal matter at
the precise time at which we have determined beforehand to
consider it, and just when we set ourselves to do so. For the
peculiar train of thought which is favorable to it may sud-
denly become active without any special call being made upon
it, and we may then follow it up with keen interest. In this
way reflection, too, chooses its own time.
This reining-in of the imagination which I am recommend-
ing, will also forbid us to summon up the memory of the
past misfortune, to paint a dark picture of the injustice or
harm that has been done us, the losses we have sustained,
the insults, slights and annoyances to which we have been
exposed: for to do that is to rouse into fresh life all those
hateful passions long laid asleep—the anger and resentment
which disturb and pollute our nature. In an excellent par-
able, Proclus, the Neoplatonist, points out how in every town
the mob dwells side by side with those who are rich and
distinguished: so, too, in every man, be he never so noble
and dignified, there is, in the depth of his nature, a mob of
low and vulgar desires which constitute him an animal. It
will not do to let this mob revolt or even so much as peep
forth from its hiding-place; it is hideous of mien, and its
rebel leaders are those flights of imagination which I have
been describing. The smallest annoyance, whether it comes
from our fellow-men or from the things around us, may swell
up into a monster of dreadful aspect, putting us at our wits’
end—and all because we go on brooding over our troubles
and painting them in the most glaring colors and on the
largest scale. It is much better to take a very calm and prosaic
view of what is disagreeable; for that is the easiest way of
bearing it.
If you hold small objects close to your eyes, you limit your
field of vision and shut out the world. And, in the same way,
the people or the things which stand nearest, even though
they are of the very smallest consequence, are apt to claim an
amount of attention much beyond their due, occupying us
disagreeably, and leaving no room for serious thoughts and
affairs of importance. We ought to work against this ten-
dency.
41
Schopenhauer
SECTION 14. The sight of things which do not belong to
us is very apt to raise the thought: Ah, if that were only mine!
making us sensible of our privation. Instead of that we should
do better by more frequently putting to ourselves the oppo-
site case: Ah, if that were not mine. What I mean is that we
should sometimes try to look upon our possessions in the
light in which they would appear if we had lost them; what-
ever they may be, property, health, friends, a wife or child or
someone else we love, our horse or our dog—it is usually
only when we have lost them that we begin to find out their
value. But if we come to look at things in the way I recom-
mend, we shall be doubly the gainers; we shall at once get
more pleasure out of them than we did before, and we shall
do everything in our power to prevent the loss of them; for
instance, by not risking our property, or angering our friends,
or exposing our wives to temptation, or being careless about
our children’s health, and so on.
We often try to banish the gloom and despondency of the
present by speculating upon our chances of success in the
future; a process which leads us to invent a great many chi-
merical hopes. Every one of them contains the germ of illu-
sion, and disappointment is inevitable when our hopes are
shattered by the hard facts of life.
It is less hurtful to take the chances of misfortune as a
theme for speculation; because, in doing so, we provide our-
selves at once with measures of precaution against it, and a
pleasant surprise when it fails to make its appearance. Is it
not a fact that we always feel a marked improvement in our
spirits when we begin to get over a period of anxiety? I may
go further and say that there is some use in occasionally look-
ing upon terrible misfortunes—such as might happen to us—
as though they had actually happened, for then the trivial
reverses which subsequently come in reality, are much easier
to bear. It is a source of consolation to look back upon those
great misfortunes which never happened. But in following
out this rule, care must be taken not to neglect what I have
said in the preceding section.
42
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 15. The things which engage our attention—
whether they are matters of business or ordinary events—
are of such diverse kinds, that, if taken quite separately and
in no fixed order or relation, they present a medley of the
most glaring contrasts, with nothing in common, except that
they one and all affect us in particular. There must be a cor-
responding abruptness in the thoughts and anxieties which
these various matters arouse in us, if our thoughts are to be
in keeping with their various subjects. Therefore, in setting
about anything, the first step is to withdraw our attention
from everything else: this will enable us to attend to each
matter at its own time, and to enjoy or put up with it, quite
apart from any thought of our remaining interests. Our
thoughts must be arranged, as it were, in little drawers, so
that we may open one without disturbing any of the others.
In this way we can keep the heavy burden of anxiety from
weighing upon us so much as to spoil the little pleasures of
the present, or from robbing us of our rest; otherwise the
consideration of one matter will interfere with every other,
and attention to some important business may lead us to
neglect many affairs which happen to be of less moment. It
is most important for everyone who is capable of higher and
nobler thoughts to keep their mind from being so completely
engrossed with private affairs and vulgar troubles as to let
them take up all his attention and crowd out worthier mat-
ter; for that is, in a very real sense, to lose sight of the true
end of life—propter vitam vivendi perdere causas.
Of course for this—as for so much else—self-control is
necessary; without it, we cannot manage ourselves in the way
I have described. And self-control may not appear so very
difficult, if we consider that every man has to submit to a
great deal of very severe control on the part of his surround-
ings, and that without it no form of existence is possible.
Further, a little self-control at the right moment may pre-
vent much subsequent compulsion at the hands of others;
just as a very small section of a circle close to the centre may
correspond to a part near the circumference a hundred times
as large. Nothing will protect us from external compulsion
so much as the control of ourselves; and, as Seneca says, to
submit yourself to reason is the way to make everything else
submit to you—si tibi vis omnia subjicere, te subjice rationi.
Self-control, too, is something which we have in our own
43
Schopenhauer
power; and if the worst comes to the worst, and it touches us
in a very sensitive part, we can always relax its severity. But
other people will pay no regard to our feelings, if they have
to use compulsion, and we shall be treated without pity or
mercy. Therefore it will be prudent to anticipate compulsion
by self-control.
SECTION 16. We must set limits to our wishes, curb our
desires, moderate our anger, always remembering that an
individual can attain only an infinitesimal share in anything
that is worth having; and that, on the other hand, everyone
must incur many of the ills of life; in a word, we must bear
and forbear—abstinere et sustinere; and if we fail to observe
this rule, no position of wealth or power will prevent us from
feeling wretched. This is what Horace means when he rec-
ommends us to study carefully and inquire diligently what
will best promote a tranquil life—not to be always agitated
by fruitless desires and fears and hopes for things, which,
after all, are not worth very much:—
Inter cuncta leges et percontabere doctos
Qua ratione queas traducere leniter aevum;
Ne te semper inops agitet vexetque cupido,
Ne pavor, et rerum mediocriter utilium spes.
1
1 Epist. I. xviii. 97.
44
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 17. Life consists in movement, says Aristotle;
and he is obviously right. We exist, physically, because our
organism is the seat of constant motion; and if we are to
exist intellectually, it can only be by means of continual oc-
cupation—no matter with what so long as it is some form of
practical or mental activity. You may see that this is so by the
way in which people who have no work or nothing to think
about, immediately begin to beat the devil’s tattoo with their
knuckles or a stick or anything that comes handy. The truth
is, that our nature is essentially restless in its character: we
very soon get tired of having nothing to do; it is intolerable
boredom. This impulse to activity should be regulated, and
some sort of method introduced into it, which of itself will
enhance the satisfaction we obtain. Activity!—doing some-
thing, if possible creating something, at any rate learning
something—how fortunate it is that men cannot exist with-
out that! A man wants to use his strength, to see, if he can,
what effect it will produce; and he will get the most com-
plete satisfaction of this desire if he can make or construct
something—be it a book or a basket. There is a direct plea-
sure in seeing work grow under one’s hands day by day, until
at last it is finished. This is the pleasure attaching to a work
of art or a manuscript, or even mere manual labor; and, of
course, the higher the work, the greater pleasure it will give.
From this point of view, those are happiest of all who are
conscious of the power to produce great works animated by
some significant purpose: it gives a higher kind of interest—
a sort of rare flavor—to the whole of their life, which, by its
absence from the life of the ordinary man, makes it, in com-
parison, something very insipid. For richly endowed natures,
life and the world have a special interest beyond the mere
everyday personal interest which so many others share; and
something higher than that—a formal interest. It is from life
and the world that they get the material for their works; and
as soon as they are freed from the pressure of personal needs,
it is to the diligent collection of material that they devote
their whole existence. So with their intellect: it is to some
extent of a two-fold character, and devoted partly to the or-
dinary affairs of every day—those matters of will which are
common to them and the rest of mankind, and partly to
their peculiar work—the pure and objective contemplation
of existence. And while, on the stage of the world, most men
45
Schopenhauer
play their little part and then pass away, the genius lives a
double life, at once an actor and a spectator.
Let everyone, then, do something, according to the mea-
sure of his capacities. To have no regular work, no set sphere
of activity—what a miserable thing it is! How often long
travels undertaken for pleasure make a man downright un-
happy; because the absence of anything that can be called
occupation forces him, as it were, out of his right element.
Effort, struggles with difficulties! that is as natural to a man
as grubbing in the ground is to a mole. To have all his wants
satisfied is something intolerable—the feeling of stagnation
which comes from pleasures that last too long. To overcome
difficulties is to experience the full delight of existence, no
matter where the obstacles are encountered; whether in the
affairs of life, in commerce or business; or in mental effort—
the spirit of inquiry that tries to master its subject. There is
always something pleasurable in the struggle and the vic-
tory. And if a man has no opportunity to excite himself, he
will do what he can to create one, and according to his indi-
vidual bent, he will hunt or play Cup and Ball: or led on by
this unsuspected element in his nature, he will pick a quarrel
with some one, or hatch a plot or intrigue, or take to swin-
dling and rascally courses generally—all to put an end to a
state of repose which is intolerable. As I have remarked,
difficilis in otio quies—it is difficult to keep quiet if you have
nothing to do.
46
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 18. A man should avoid being led on by the
phantoms of his imagination. This is not the same thing as
to submit to the guidance of ideas clearly thought out: and
yet these are rules of life which most people pervert. If you
examine closely into the circumstances which, in any delib-
eration, ultimately turn the scale in favor of some particular
course, you will generally find that the decision is influenced,
not by any clear arrangement of ideas leading to a formal
judgment, but by some fanciful picture which seems to stand
for one of the alternatives in question.
In one of Voltaire’s or Diderot’s romances,—I forget the
precise reference,—the hero, standing like a young Hercules
at the parting of ways, can see no other representation of
Virtue than his old tutor holding a snuff-box in his left hand,
from which he takes a pinch and moralizes; whilst Vice ap-
pears in the shape of his mother’s chambermaid. It is in youth,
more especially, that the goal of our efforts comes to be a
fanciful picture of happiness, which continues to hover be-
fore our eyes sometimes for half and even for the whole of
our life—a sort of mocking spirit; for when we think our
dream is to be realized, the picture fades away, leaving us the
knowledge that nothing of what it promised is actually ac-
complished. How often this is so with the visions of domes-
ticity—the detailed picture of what our home will be like;
or, of life among our fellow-citizens or in society; or, again,
of living in the country—the kind of house we shall have, its
surroundings, the marks of honor and respect that will be
paid to us, and so on,—whatever our hobby may be; chaque
fou a sa marotte. It is often the same, too, with our dreams
about one we love. And this is all quite natural; for the vi-
sions we conjure up affect us directly, as though they were
real objects; and so they exercise a more immediate influ-
ence upon our will than an abstract idea, which gives merely
a vague, general outline, devoid of details; and the details are
just the real part of it. We can be only indirectly affected by
an abstract idea, and yet it is the abstract idea alone which
will do as much as it promises; and it is the function of edu-
cation to teach us to put our trust in it. Of course the ab-
stract idea must be occasionally explained—paraphrased, as
it were—by the aid of pictures; but discreetly, cum grano salis.
47
Schopenhauer
SECTION 19. The preceding rule may be taken as a special
case of the more general maxim, that a man should never let
himself be mastered by the impressions of the moment, or
indeed by outward appearances at all, which are incompara-
bly more powerful in their effects than the mere play of
thought or a train of ideas; not because these momentary
impressions are rich in virtue of the data they supply,—it is
often just the contrary,—but because they are something
palpable to the senses and direct in their working; they forc-
ibly invade our mind, disturbing our repose and shattering
our resolutions.
It is easy to understand that the thing which lies before
our very eyes will produce the whole of its effect at once, but
that time and leisure are necessary for the working of thought
and the appreciation of argument, as it is impossible to think
of everything at one and the same moment. This is why we
are so allured by pleasure, in spite of all our determination to
resist it; or so much annoyed by a criticism, even though we
know that its author it totally incompetent to judge; or so
irritated by an insult, though it comes from some very con-
temptible quarter. In the same way, to mention no other
instances, ten reasons for thinking that there is no danger
may be outweighed by one mistaken notion that it is actu-
ally at hand. All this shows the radical unreason of human
nature. Women frequently succumb altogether to this pre-
dominating influence of present impressions, and there are
few men so overweighted with reason as to escape suffering
from a similar cause.
If it is impossible to resist the effects of some external in-
fluence by the mere play of thought, the best thing to do is
to neutralize it by some contrary influence; for example, the
effect of an insult may be overcome by seeking the society of
those who have a good opinion of us; and the unpleasant
sensation of imminent danger may be avoided by fixing our
attention on the means of warding it off.
Leibnitz
1
tells of an Italian who managed to bear up un-
der the tortures of the rack by never for a moment ceasing to
think of the gallows which would have awaited him, had he
revealed his secret; he kept on crying out: I see it! I see it!—
afterwards explaining that this was part of his plan.
It is from some such reason as this, that we find it so diffi-
1 Nouveaux Essais. Liv. I. ch. 2. Sec. 11.
48
Essays – Volume One
cult to stand alone in a matter of opinion,—not to be made
irresolute by the fact that everyone else disagrees with us and
acts accordingly, even though we are quite sure that they are
in the wrong. Take the case of a fugitive king who is trying to
avoid capture; how much consolation he must find in the
ceremonious and submissive attitude of a faithful follower,
exhibited secretly so as not to betray his master’s strict incog-
nito; it must be almost necessary to prevent him doubting
his own existence.
SECTION 20. In the first part of this work I have insisted
upon the great value of health as the chief and most impor-
tant element in happiness. Let me emphasize and confirm
what I have there said by giving a few general rules as to its
preservation.
The way to harden the body is to impose a great deal of
labor and effort upon it in the days of good health,—to ex-
ercise it, both as a whole and in its several parts, and to ha-
bituate it to withstand all kinds of noxious influences. But
on the appearance of an illness or disorder, either in the body
as a whole or in many of its parts, a contrary course should
be taken, and every means used to nurse the body, or the
part of it which is affected, and to spare it any effort; for
what is ailing and debilitated cannot be hardened.
The muscles may be strengthened by a vigorous use of them;
but not so the nerves; they are weakened by it. Therefore,
while exercising the muscles in every way that is suitable, care
should be taken to spare the nerves as much as possible. The
eyes, for instance, should be protected from too strong a
light,—especially when it is reflected light,—from any strain-
ing of them in the dark, or from the long-continued examina-
49
Schopenhauer
tion of minute objects; and the ears from too loud sounds.
Above all, the brain should never be forced, or used too much,
or at the wrong time; let it have a rest during digestion; for
then the same vital energy which forms thoughts in the brain
has a great deal of work to do elsewhere,—I mean in the di-
gestive organs, where it prepares chyme and chyle. For similar
reasons, the brain should never be used during, or immedi-
ately after, violent muscular exercise. For the motor nerves are
in this respect on a par with the sensory nerves; the pain felt
when a limb is wounded has its seat in the brain; and, in the
same way, it is not really our legs and arms which work and
move,—it is the brain, or, more strictly, that part of it which,
through the medium of the spine, excites the nerves in the
limbs and sets them in motion. Accordingly, when our arms
and legs feel tired, the true seat of this feeling is in the brain.
This is why it is only in connection with those muscles which
are set in motion consciously and voluntarily,—in other words,
depend for their action upon the brain,—that any feeling of
fatigue can arise; this is not the case with those muscles which
work involuntarily, like the heart. It is obvious, then, that in-
jury is done to the brain if violent muscular exercise and intel-
lectual exertion are forced upon it at the same moment, or at
very short intervals.
What I say stands in no contradiction with the fact that at
the beginning of a walk, or at any period of a short stroll, there
often comes a feeling of enhanced intellectual vigor. The parts
of the brain that come into play have had no time to become
tired; and besides, slight muscular exercise conduces to activ-
ity of the respiratory organs, and causes a purer and more
oxydated supply of arterial blood to mount to the brain.
It is most important to allow the brain the full measure of
sleep which is required to restore it; for sleep is to a man’s whole
nature what winding up is to a clock.
1
This measure will vary
directly with the development and activity of the brain; to over-
step the measure is mere waste of time, because if that is done,
sleep gains only so much in length as it loses in depth.
2
1 Of. Welt als Wille und Vorstellung, 4th Edition. Bk. II. pp.
236-40.
2 Cf. loc: cit: p. 275. Sleep is a morsel of death borrowed to
keep up and renew the part of life which is exhausted by the
day—le sommeil est un emprunt fait à la mort. Or it might be
said that sleep is the interest we have to pay on the capital
which is called in at death; and the higher the rate of interest
and the more regularly it is paid, the further the date of re-
demption is postponed.
50
Essays – Volume One
It should be clearly understood that thought is nothing
but the organic function of the brain; and it has to obey the
same laws in regard to exertion and repose as any other or-
ganic function. The brain can be ruined by overstrain, just
like the eyes. As the function of the stomach is to digest, so it
is that of the brain to think. The notion of a soul,—as some-
thing elementary and immaterial, merely lodging in the brain
and needing nothing at all for the performance of its essen-
tial function, which consists in always and unweariedly think-
ing—has undoubtedly driven many people to foolish prac-
tices, leading to a deadening of the intellectual powers;
Frederick the Great, even, once tried to form the habit of
doing without sleep altogether. It would be well if professors
of philosophy refrained from giving currency to a notion
which is attended by practical results of a pernicious charac-
ter; but then this is just what professorial philosophy does,
in its old-womanish endeavor to keep on good terms with
the catechism. A man should accustom himself to view his
intellectual capacities in no other light than that of physi-
ological functions, and to manage them accordingly—nurs-
ing or exercising them as the case may be; remembering that
every kind of physical suffering, malady or disorder, in what-
ever part of the body it occurs, has its effect upon the mind.
The best advice that I know on this subject is given by Cabanis
in his Rapports du physique et du moral de l’homme.
1
Through neglect of this rule, many men of genius and great
scholars have become weak-minded and childish, or even
gone quite mad, as they grew old. To take no other instances,
there can be no doubt that the celebrated English poets of
the early part of this century, Scott, Wordsworth, Southey,
became intellectually dull and incapable towards the end of
their days, nay, soon after passing their sixtieth year; and
that their imbecility can be traced to the fact that, at that
period of life, they were all led on? by the promise of high
pay, to treat literature as a trade and to write for money. This
seduced them into an unnatural abuse of their intellectual
powers; and a man who puts his Pegasus into harness, and
1 Translator’s Note. The work to which Schopenhauer here
refers is a series of essays by Cabanis, a French philosopher
(1757-1808), treating of mental and moral phenomena on a
physiological basis. In his later days, Cabanis completely
abandoned his materialistic standpoint.
51
Schopenhauer
urges on his Muse with the whip, will have to pay a penalty
similar to that which is exacted by the abuse of other kinds
of power.
And even in the case of Kant, I suspect that the second
childhood of his last four years was due to overwork in later
life, and after he had succeeded in becoming a famous man.
Every month of the year has its own peculiar and direct
influence upon health and bodily condition generally; nay,
even upon the state of the mind. It is an influence depen-
dent upon the weather.
CHAPTER III
CHAPTER III
CHAPTER III
CHAPTER III
CHAPTER III
OUR REL
OUR REL
OUR REL
OUR REL
OUR RELA
A
A
A
ATION
TION
TION
TION
TION T
T
T
T
TO O
O O
O O
O O
O OTHERS.—SECTION 21.
THERS.—SECTION 21.
THERS.—SECTION 21.
THERS.—SECTION 21.
THERS.—SECTION 21.
I
N
MAKING
HIS
WAY
THROUGH
LIFE
, a man will find it useful to
be ready and able to do two things: to look ahead and to
overlook: the one will protect him from loss and injury, the
other from disputes and squabbles.
No one who has to live amongst men should absolutely
discard any person who has his due place in the order of
nature, even though he is very wicked or contemptible or
ridiculous. He must accept him as an unalterable fact—un-
alterable, because the necessary outcome of an eternal, fun-
damental principle; and in bad cases he should remember
the words of Mephistopheles: es muss auch solche Käuze
geben
1
—there must be fools and rogues in the world. If he
acts otherwise, he will be committing an injustice, and giv-
ing a challenge of life and death to the man he discards. No
one can alter his own peculiar individuality, his moral char-
acter, his intellectual capacity, his temperament or physique;
1 Goethe’s Faust, Part I.
52
Essays – Volume One
and if we go so far as to condemn a man from every point of
view, there will be nothing left him but to engage us in deadly
conflict; for we are practically allowing him the right to exist
only on condition that he becomes another man—which is
impossible; his nature forbids it.
So if you have to live amongst men, you must allow every-
one the right to exist in accordance with the character he
has, whatever it turns out to be: and all you should strive to
do is to make use of this character in such a way as its kind
and nature permit, rather than to hope for any alteration in
it, or to condemn it off-hand for what it is. This is the true
sense of the maxim—Live and let live. That, however, is a
task which is difficult in proportion as it is right; and he is a
happy man who can once for all avoid having to do with a
great many of his fellow creatures.
The art of putting up with people may be learned by prac-
ticing patience on inanimate objects, which, in virtue of some
mechanical or general physical necessity, oppose a stubborn
resistance to our freedom of action—a form of patience which
is required every day. The patience thus gained may be ap-
plied to our dealings with men, by accustoming ourselves to
regard their opposition, wherever we encounter it, as the in-
evitable outcome of their nature, which sets itself up against
us in virtue of the same rigid law of necessity as governs the
resistance of inanimate objects. To become indignant at their
conduct is as foolish as to be angry with a stone because it
rolls into your path. And with many people the wisest thing
you can do, is to resolve to make use of those whom you
cannot alter.
53
Schopenhauer
SECTION 22. It is astonishing how easily and how quickly
similarity, or difference of mind and disposition, makes it-
self felt between one man and another as soon as they begin
to talk: every little trifle shows it. When two people of to-
tally different natures are conversing, almost everything said
by the one will, in a greater or less degree, displease the other,
and in many cases produce positive annoyance; even though
the conversation turn upon the most out-of-the-way sub-
ject, or one in which neither of the parties has any real inter-
est. People of similar nature, on the other hand, immedi-
ately come to feel a kind of general agreement; and if they
are cast very much in the same mould, complete harmony or
even unison will flow from their intercourse.
This explain two circumstances. First of all, it shows why
it is that common, ordinary people are so sociable and find
good company wherever they go. Ah! those good, dear, brave
people. It is just the contrary with those who are not of the
common run; and the less they are so, the more unsociable
they become; so that if, in their isolation, they chance to
come across some one in whose nature they can find even a
single sympathetic chord, be it never so minute, they show
extraordinary pleasure in his society. For one man can be to
another only so much as the other is to him. Great minds are
like eagles, and build their nest in some lofty solitude.
Secondly, we are enabled to understand how it is that people
of like disposition so quickly get on with one another, as
though they were drawn together by magnetic force—kin-
dred souls greeting each other from afar. Of course the most
frequent opportunity of observing this is afforded by people
of vulgar tastes and inferior intellect, but only because their
name is legion; while those who are better off in this respect
and of a rarer nature, are not often to be met with: they are
called rare because you can seldom find them.
Take the case of a large number of people who have formed
themselves into a league for the purpose of carrying out some
practical object; if there be two rascals among them, they
will recognize each other as readily as if they bore a similar
badge, and will at once conspire for some misfeasance or
treachery. In the same way, if you can imagine—per impos-
sible—a large company of very intelligent and clever people,
amongst whom there are only two blockheads, these two
will be sure to be drawn together by a feeling of sympathy,
54
Essays – Volume One
and each of them will very soon secretly rejoice at having
found at least one intelligent person in the whole company.
It is really quite curious to see how two such men, especially
if they are morally and intellectually of an inferior type, will
recognize each other at first sight; with what zeal they will
strive to become intimate; how affably and cheerily they will
run to greet each other, just as though they were old friends;—
it is all so striking that one is tempted to embrace the Bud-
dhist doctrine of metempsychosis and presume that they were
on familiar terms in some former state of existence.
Still, in spite of all this general agreement, men are kept
apart who might come together; or, in some cases, a passing
discord springs up between them. This is due to diversity of
mood. You will hardly ever see two people exactly in the
same frame of mind; for that is something which varies with
their condition of life, occupation, surroundings, health, the
train of thought they are in at the moment, and so on. These
differences give rise to discord between persons of the most
harmonious disposition. To correct the balance properly, so
as to remove the disturbance—to introduce, as it were, a
uniform temperature,—is a work demanding a very high
degree of culture. The extent to which uniformity of mood
is productive of good-fellowship may be measured by its ef-
fects upon a large company. When, for instance, a great many
people are gathered together and presented with some ob-
jective interest which works upon all alike and influences
them in a similar way, no matter what it be—a common
danger or hope, some great news, a spectacle, a play, a piece
of music, or anything of that kind—you will find them roused
to a mutual expression of thought, and a display of sincere
interest. There will be a general feeling of pleasure amongst
them; for that which attracts their attention produces a unity
of mood by overpowering all private and personal interests.
And in default of some objective interest of the kind I have
mentioned, recourse is usually had to something subjective.
A bottle of wine is not an uncommon means of introducing
a mutual feeling of fellowship; and even tea and coffee are
used for a like end.
The discord which so easily finds its way into all society as
an effect of the different moods in which people happen to
be for the moment, also in part explains why it is that memory
always idealizes, and sometimes almost transfigures, the atti-
55
Schopenhauer
tude we have taken up at any period of the past—a change
due to our inability to remember all the fleeting influences
which disturbed us on any given occasion. Memory is in this
respect like the lens of a camera obscura: it contracts every-
thing within its range, and so produces a much finer picture
than the actual landscape affords. And, in the case of a man,
absence always goes some way towards securing this advan-
tageous light; for though the idealizing tendency of the
memory requires times to complete its work, it begins it at
once. Hence it is a prudent thing to see your friends and
acquaintances only at considerable intervals of time; and on
meeting them again, you will observe that memory has been
at work.
SECTION 23. No man can see over his own height. Let me
explain what I mean.
You cannot see in another man any more than you have in
yourself; and your own intelligence strictly determines the
extent to which he comes within its grasp. If your intelli-
gence is of a very low order, mental qualities in another, even
though they be of the highest kind, will have no effect at all
upon you; you will see nothing in their possessor except the
meanest side of his individuality—in other words, just those
parts of his character and disposition which are weak and
defective. Your whole estimate of the man will be confined
to his defects, and his higher mental qualities will no more
exist for you than colors exist for those who cannot see.
Intellect is invisible to the man who has none. In any at-
tempt to criticise another’s work, the range of knowledge
possessed by the critic is as essential a part of his verdict as
the claims of the work itself.
Hence intercourse with others involves a process of level-
ing down. The qualities which are present in one man, and
absent in another, cannot come into play when they meet;
and the self-sacrifice which this entails upon one of the par-
56
Essays – Volume One
ties, calls forth no recognition from the other.
Consider how sordid, how stupid, in a word, how vulgar
most men are, and you will see that it is impossible to talk to
them without becoming vulgar yourself for the time being.
Vulgarity is in this respect like electricity; it is easily distrib-
uted. You will then fully appreciate the truth and propriety
of the expression, to make yourself cheap; and you will be glad
to avoid the society of people whose only possible point of
contact with you is just that part of your nature of which
you have least reason to be proud. So you will see that, in
dealing with fools and blockheads, there is only one way of
showing your intelligence—by having nothing to do with
them. That means, of course, that when you go into society,
you may now and then feel like a good dancer who gets an
invitation to a ball, and on arriving, finds that everyone is
lame:—with whom is he to dance?
SECTION 24. I feel respect for the man—and he is one in
a hundred—who, when he is waiting or sitting unoccupied,
refrains from rattling or beating time with anything that
happens to be handy,—his stick, or knife and fork, or what-
ever else it may be. The probability is that he is thinking of
something.
With a large number of people, it is quite evident that
their power of sight completely dominates over their power
of thought; they seem to be conscious of existence only when
they are making a noise; unless indeed they happen to be
smoking, for this serves a similar end. It is for the same rea-
son that they never fail to be all eyes and ears for what is
going on around them.
57
Schopenhauer
SECTION 25. La Rochefoucauld makes the striking remark
that it is difficult to feel deep veneration and great affection
for one and the same person. If this is so, we shall have to
choose whether it is veneration or love that we want from
our fellow-men.
Their love is always selfish, though in very different ways;
and the means used to gain it are not always of a kind to
make us proud. A man is loved by others mainly in the de-
gree in which he moderates his claim on their good feeling
and intelligence: but he must act genuinely in the matter
and without dissimulation—not merely out of forbearance,
which is at bottom a kind of contempt. This calls to mind a
very true observation of Helvetius
1
: the amount of intellect
necessary to please us, is a most accurate measure of the amount
of intellect we have ourselves. With these remarks as premises,
it is easy to draw the conclusion.
1 Translator’s Note. Helvetius, Claude-Adrien (1715-71), a
French philosophical writer much esteemed by
Schopenhauer. His chief work, De l’Esprit, excited great in-
terest and opposition at the time of its publication, on ac-
count of the author’s pronounced materialism.
Now with veneration the case is just the opposite; it is wrung
from men reluctantly, and for that very reason mostly con-
cealed. Hence, as compared with love, veneration gives more
real satisfaction; for it is connected with personal value, and
the same is not directly true of love, which is subjective in its
nature, whilst veneration is objective. To be sure, it is more
useful to be loved than to be venerated.
58
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 26. Most men are so thoroughly subjective that
nothing really interests them but themselves. They always
think of their own case as soon as ever any remark is made,
and their whole attention is engrossed and absorbed by the
merest chance reference to anything which affects them per-
sonally, be it never so remote: with the result that they have
no power left for forming an objective view of things, should
the conversation take that turn; neither can they admit any
validity in arguments which tell against their interest or their
vanity. Hence their attention is easily distracted. They are so
readily offended, insulted or annoyed, that in discussing any
impersonal matter with them, no care is too great to avoid
letting your remarks bear the slightest possible reference to
the very worthy and sensitive individuals whom you have
before you; for anything you may say will perhaps hurt their
feelings. People really care about nothing that does not af-
fect them personally. True and striking observations, fine,
subtle and witty things are lost upon them: they cannot un-
derstand or feel them. But anything that disturbs their petty
vanity in the most remote and indirect way, or reflects preju-
dicially upon their exceedingly precious selves—to that, they
are most tenderly sensitive. In this respect they are like the
little dog whose toes you are so apt to tread upon inadvert-
ently—you know it by the shrill bark it sets up: or, again,
they resemble a sick man covered with sores and boils, with
whom the greatest care must be taken to avoid unnecessary
handling. And in some people this feeling reaches such a
pass that, if they are talking with anyone, and he exhibits, or
does not sufficiently conceal, his intelligence and discern-
ment, they look upon it as a downright insult; although for
the moment they hide their ill will, and the unsuspecting
author of it afterwards ruminates in vain upon their con-
duct, and racks his brain to discover what he could possibly
have done to excite their malice and hatred.
But it is just as easy to flatter and win them over; and this
is why their judgment is usually corrupt, and why their opin-
ions are swayed, not by what is really true and right, but by
the favor of the party or class to which they belong. And the
ultimate reason of it all is, that in such people force of will
greatly predominates over knowledge; and hence their mea-
gre intellect is wholly given up to the service of the will, and
can never free itself from that service for a moment.
59
Schopenhauer
Astrology furnishes a magnificent proof of this miserable
subjective tendency in men, which leads them to see every-
thing only as bearing upon themselves, and to think of noth-
ing that is not straightway made into a personal matter. The
aim of astrology is to bring the motions of the celestial bod-
ies into relation with the wretched Ego and to establish a
connection between a comet in the sky and squabbles and
rascalities on earth.
1
1 See, for instance, Stobasus, Eclog. I. xxii. 9.
SECTION 27. When any wrong statement is made, whether
in public or in society, or in books, and well received—or, at
any rate, not refuted—that that is no reason why you should
despair or think there the matter will rest. You should com-
fort yourself with the reflection that the question will be af-
terwards gradually subjected to examination; light will be
thrown upon it; it will be thought over, considered, discussed,
and generally in the end the correct view will be reached; so
that, after a time—the length of which will depend upon
the difficulty of the subject—everyone will come to under-
stand that which a clear head saw at once.
In the meantime, of course, you must have patience. He
who can see truly in the midst of general infatuation is like a
man whose watch keeps good time, when all clocks in the
town in which he lives are wrong. He alone knows the right
time; but what use is that to him? for everyone goes by the
clocks which speak false, not even excepting those who know
that his watch is the only one that is right.
60
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 28. Men are like children, in that, if you spoil
them, they become naughty.
Therefore it is well not to be too indulgent or charitable
with anyone. You may take it as a general rule that you will
not lose a friend by refusing him a loan, but that you are
very likely to do so by granting it; and, for similar reasons,
you will not readily alienate people by being somewhat proud
and careless in your behaviour; but if you are very kind and
complaisant towards them, you will often make them arro-
gant and intolerable, and so a breach will ensue.
There is one thing that, more than any other, throws people
absolutely off their balance—the thought that you are de-
pendent upon them. This is sure to produce an insolent and
domineering manner towards you. There are some people,
indeed, who become rude if you enter into any kind of rela-
tion with them; for instance, if you have occasion to con-
verse with them frequently upon confidential matters, they
soon come to fancy that they can take liberties with you,
and so they try and transgress the laws of politeness. This is
why there are so few with whom you care to become more
intimate, and why you should avoid familiarity with vulgar
people. If a man comes to think that I am more dependent
upon him than he is upon me, he at once feels as though I
had stolen something from him; and his endeavor will be to
have his vengeance and get it back. The only way to attain
superiority in dealing with men, is to let it be seen that you
are independent of them.
And in this view it is advisable to let everyone of your ac-
quaintance—whether man or woman—feel now and then
that you could very well dispense with their company. This
will consolidate friendship. Nay, with most people there will
be no harm in occasionally mixing a grain of disdain with
your treatment of them; that will make them value your
friendship all the more. Chi non istima vien stimato, as a subtle
Italian proverb has it—to disregard is to win regard. But if
we really think very highly of a person, we should conceal it
from him like a crime. This is not a very gratifying thing to
do, but it is right. Why, a dog will not bear being treated too
kindly, let alone a man!
61
Schopenhauer
SECTION 29. It is often the case that people of noble char-
acter and great mental gifts betray a strange lack of worldly
wisdom and a deficiency in the knowledge of men, more
especially when they are young; with the result that it is easy
to deceive or mislead them; and that, on the other hand,
natures of the commoner sort are more ready and successful
in making their way in the world.
The reason of this is that, when a man has little or no
experience, he must judge by his own antecedent notions;
and in matters demanding judgment, an antecedent notion
is never on the same level as experience. For, with the com-
moner sort of people, an antecedent notion means just their
own selfish point of view. This is not the case with those
whose mind and character are above the ordinary; for it is
precisely in this respect—their unselfishness—that they dif-
fer from the rest of mankind; and as they judge other people’s
thoughts and actions by their own high standard, the result
does not always tally with their calculation.
But if, in the end, a man of noble character comes to see,
as the effect of his own experience, or by the lessons he learns
from others, what it is that may be expected of men in gen-
eral,—namely, that five-sixths of them are morally and in-
tellectually so constituted that, if circumstances do not place
you in relation with them, you had better get out of their
way and keep as far as possible from having anything to do
with them,—still, he will scarcely ever attain an adequate
notion of their wretchedly mean and shabby nature: all his
life long he will have to be extending and adding to the infe-
rior estimate he forms of them; and in the meantime he will
commit a great many mistakes and do himself harm.
Then, again, after he has really taken to heart the lessons
that have been taught him, it will occasionally happen that,
when he is in the society of people whom he does not know,
he will be surprised to find how thoroughly reasonable they
all appear to be, both in their conversation and in their de-
meanor—in fact, quite honest, sincere, virtuous and trust-
worthy people, and at the same time shrewd and clever.
But that ought not to perplex him. Nature is not like those
bad poets, who, in setting a fool or a knave before us, do
their work so clumsily, and with such evident design, that
you might almost fancy you saw the poet standing behind
each of his characters, and continually disavowing their sen-
62
Essays – Volume One
timents, and telling you in a tone of warning: This is a knave;
that is a fool; do not mind what he says. But Nature goes to
work like Shakespeare and Goethe, poets who make every
one of their characters—even if it is the devil himself!—ap-
pear to be quite in the right for the moment that they come
before us in their several parts; the characters are described
so objectively that they excite our interest and compel us to
sympathize with their point of view; for, like the works of
Nature, every one of these characters is evolved as the result
of some hidden law or principle, which makes all they say
and do appear natural and therefore necessary. And you will
always be the prey or the plaything of the devils and fools in
this world, if you expect to see them going about with horns
or jangling their bells.
And it should be borne in mind that, in their intercourse
with others, people are like the moon, or like hunchbacks;
they show you only one of their sides. Every man has an
innate talent for mimicry,—for making a mask out of his
physiognomy, so that he can always look as if he really were
what he pretends to be; and since he makes his calculations
always within the lines of his individual nature, the appear-
ance he puts on suits him to a nicety, and its effect is ex-
tremely deceptive. He dons his mask whenever his object is
to flatter himself into some one’s good opinion; and you may
pay just as much attention to it as if it were made of wax or
cardboard, never forgetting that excellent Italian proverb: non
é si tristo cane che non meni la coda,—there is no dog so bad
but that he will wag his tail.
In any case it is well to take care not to form a highly
favorable opinion of a person whose acquaintance you have
only recently made, for otherwise you are very likely to be
disappointed; and then you will be ashamed of yourself and
perhaps even suffer some injury. And while I am on the sub-
ject, there is another fact that deserves mention. It is this. A
man shows his character just in the way in which he deals
with trifles,—for then he is off his guard. This will often
afford a good opportunity of observing the boundless ego-
ism of man’s nature, and his total lack of consideration for
others; and if these defects show themselves in small things,
or merely in his general demeanor, you will find that they
also underlie his action in matters of importance, although
he may disguise the fact. This is an opportunity which should
63
Schopenhauer
not be missed. If in the little affairs of every day,—the trifles
of life, those matters to which the rule de minimis non ap-
plies,—a man is inconsiderate and seeks only what is advan-
tageous or convenient to himself, to the prejudice of others’
rights; if he appropriates to himself that which belongs to all
alike, you may be sure there is no justice in his heart, and
that he would be a scoundrel on a wholesale scale, only that
law and compulsion bind his hands. Do not trust him be-
yond your door. He who is not afraid to break the laws of his
own private circle, will break those of the State when he can
do so with impunity.
If the average man were so constituted that the good in
him outweighed the bad, it would be more advisable to rely
upon his sense of justice, fairness, gratitude, fidelity, love or
compassion, than to work upon his fears; but as the contrary
is the case, and it is the bad that outweighs the good, the
opposite course is the more prudent one.
If any person with whom we are associated or have to do,
exhibits unpleasant or annoying qualities, we have only to
ask ourselves whether or not this person is of so much value
to us that we can put up with frequent and repeated exhibi-
tions of the same qualities in a somewhat aggravated form.
1
In case of an affirmative answer to this question, there will
not be much to be said, because talking is very little use. We
must let the matter pass, with or without some notice; but
we should nevertheless remember that we are thereby expos-
ing ourselves to a repetition of the offence. If the answer is in
the negative, we must break with our worthy friend at once
and forever; or in the case of a servant, dismiss him. For he
will inevitably repeat the offence, or do something tanta-
mount to it, should the occasion return, even though for the
moment he is deep and sincere in his assurances of the con-
trary. There is nothing, absolutely nothing, that a man can-
not forget,—but not himself, his own character. For character
is incorrigible; because all a man’s actions emanate from an
inward principle, in virtue of which he must always do the
same thing under like circumstances; and he cannot do oth-
erwise. Let me refer to my prize essay on the so-called Free-
dom of the Will, the perusal of which will dissipate any delu-
sions the reader may have on this subject.
1 To forgive and forget means to throw away dearly bought
experience.
64
Essays – Volume One
To become reconciled to a friend with whom you have
broken, is a form of weakness; and you pay the penalty of it
when he takes the first opportunity of doing precisely the
very thing which brought about the breach; nay, he does it
the more boldly, because he is secretly conscious that you
cannot get on without him. This is also applicable to ser-
vants whom you have dismissed, and then taken into your
service again.
For the same reason, you should just as little expect people
to continue to act in a similar way under altered circum-
stances. The truth is that men alter their demeanor and sen-
timents just as fast as their interest changes; and their resign
in this respect is a bill drawn for short payment that the man
must be still more short-sighted who accepts the bill with-
out protesting it. Accordingly, suppose you want to know
how a man will behave in an office into which you think of
putting him; you should not build upon expectations, on
his promises or assurances. For, even allowing that he is quite
sincere, he is speaking about a matter of which he has no
knowledge. The only way to calculate how he will behave, is
to consider the circumstances in which he will be placed,
and the extent to which they will conflict with his character.
If you wish to get a clear and profound insight—and it is
very needful—into the true but melancholy elements of
which most men are made, you will find in a very instructive
thing to take the way they behave in the pages of literature as
a commentary to their doings in practical life, and vice versa.
The experience thus gained will be very useful in avoiding
wrong ideas, whether about yourself or about others. But if
you come across any special trait of meanness or stupidity—
in life or in literature,—you must be careful not to let it
annoy or distress you, but to look upon it merely as an addi-
tion to your knowledge—a new fact to be considered in study-
ing the character of humanity. Your attitude towards it will
be that of the mineralogist who stumbles upon a very char-
acteristic specimen of a mineral.
Of course there are some facts which are very exceptional,
and it is difficult to understand how they arise, and how it is
that there come to be such enormous differences between
man and man; but, in general, what was said long ago is
quite true, and the world is in a very bad way. In savage
countries they eat one another, in civilized they deceive one
65
Schopenhauer
another; and that is what people call the way of the world!
What are States and all the elaborate systems of political
machinery, and the rule of force, whether in home or in for-
eign affairs,—what are they but barriers against the bound-
less iniquity of mankind? Does not all history show that
whenever a king is firmly planted on a throne, and his people
reach some degree of prosperity, he uses it to lead his army,
like a band of robbers, against adjoining countries? Are not
almost all wars ultimately undertaken for purposes of plun-
der? In the most remote antiquity, and to some extent also in
the Middle Ages, the conquered became slaves,—in other
words, they had to work for those who conquered them; and
where is the difference between that and paying war-taxes,
which represent the product of our previous work?
All war, says Voltaire, is a matter of robbery; and the Ger-
mans should take that as a warning.
SECTION 30. No man is so formed that he can be left
entirely to himself, to go his own ways; everyone needs to be
guided by a preconceived plan, and to follow certain general
rules. But if this is carried too far, and a man tries to take on
a character which is not natural or innate in him, but it arti-
ficially acquired and evolved merely by a process of reason-
ing, he will very soon discover that Nature cannot be forced,
and that if you drive it out, it will return despite your ef-
forts:—
Naturam expelles furca, tamen usque recurret.
To understand a rule governing conduct towards others, even
to discover it for oneself and to express it neatly, is easy
enough; and still, very soon afterwards, the rule may be bro-
ken in practice. But that is no reason for despair; and you
need not fancy that as it is impossible to regulate your life in
accordance with abstract ideas and maxims, it is better to
live just as you please. Here, as in all theoretical instruction
that aims at a practical result, the first thing to do is to un-
derstand the rule; the second thing is to learn the practice of
66
Essays – Volume One
it. The theory may be understand at once by an effort of
reason, and yet the practice of it acquired only in course of
time.
A pupil may lean the various notes on an instrument of
music, or the different position in fencing; and when he
makes a mistake, as he is sure to do, however hard he tries,
he is apt to think it will be impossible to observe the rules,
when he is set to read music at sight or challenged to a furi-
ous duel. But for all that, gradual practice makes him per-
fect, through a long series of slips, blunders and fresh efforts.
It is just the same in other things; in learning to write and
speak Latin, a man will forget the grammatical rules; it is
only by long practice that a blockhead turns into a courtier,
that a passionate man becomes shrewd and worldly-wise, or
a frank person reserved, or a noble person ironical. But though
self-discipline of this kind is the result of long habit, it al-
ways works by a sort of external compulsion, which Nature
never ceases to resist and sometimes unexpectedly overcomes.
The difference between action in accordance with abstract
principles, and action as the result of original, innate ten-
dency, is the same as that between a work of art, say a watch—
where form and movement are impressed upon shapeless and
inert matter—and a living organism, where form and mat-
ter are one, and each is inseparable from the other.
There is a maxim attributed to the Emperor Napoleon,
which expresses this relation between acquired and innate
character, and confirms what I have said: everything that is
unnatural is imperfect;—a rule of universal application,
whether in the physical or in the moral sphere. The only
exception I can think of to this rule is aventurine,
1
a sub-
stance known to mineralogists, which in its natural state can-
not compare with the artificial preparation of it.
And in this connection let me utter a word of protest against
any and every form of affectation. It always arouses contempt;
in the first place, because it argues deception, and the decep-
tion is cowardly, for it is based on fear; and, secondly, it argues
self-condemnation, because it means that a man is trying to
appear what he is not, and therefore something which he things
1 Translator’s Note. Aventurine is a rare kind of quartz; and the
same name is given to a brownish-colored glass much resem-
bling it, which is manufactured at Murano. It is so called from
the fact that the glass was discovered by chance (arventura).
67
Schopenhauer
better than he actually is. To affect a quality, and to plume
yourself upon it, is just to confess that you have not got it.
Whether it is courage, or learning, or intellect, or wit, or suc-
cess with women, or riches, or social position, or whatever else
it may be that a man boasts of, you may conclude by his boast-
ing about it that that is precisely the direction in which he is
rather weak; for if a man really possesses any faculty to the
full, it will not occur to him to make a great show of affecting
it; he is quite content to know that he has it. That is the appli-
cation of the Spanish proverb: herradura que chacolotea clavo
le falta—a clattering hoof means a nail gone. To be sure, as I
said at first, no man ought to let the reins go quite loose, and
show himself just as he is; for there are many evil and bestial
sides to our nature which require to be hidden away out of
sight; and this justifies the negative attitude of dissimulation,
but it does not justify a positive feigning of qualities which are
not there. It should also be remembered that affectation is
recognized at once, even before it is clear what it is that is
being affected. And, finally, affectation cannot last very long,
and one day the mask will fall off. Nemo potest personam diu
ferre fictam, says Seneca;
1
ficta cito in naturam suam recidunt—
no one can persevere long in a fictitious character; for nature
will soon reassert itself.
1 De Clementia, I. 1.
68
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 31. A man bears the weight of his own body
without knowing it, but he soon feels the weight of any other,
if he tries to move it; in the same way, a man can see other
people’s shortcoming’s and vices, but he is blind to his own.
This arrangement has one advantage: it turns other people
into a kind of mirror, in which a man can see clearly every-
thing that is vicious, faulty, ill-bred and loathsome in his
own nature; only, it is generally the old story of the dog bark-
ing at is own image; it is himself that he sees and not another
dog, as he fancies.
He who criticises others, works at the reformation of him-
self. Those who form the secret habit of scrutinizing other
people’s general behavior, and passing severe judgment upon
what they do and leave undone, thereby improve themselves,
and work out their own perfection: for they will have suffi-
cient sense of justice, or at any rate enough pride and vanity,
to avoid in their own case that which they condemn so harshly
elsewhere. But tolerant people are just the opposite, and claim
for themselves the same indulgence that they extend to oth-
ers—hanc veniam damus petimusque vicissim. It is all very
well for the Bible to talk about the mote in another’s eye and
the beam in one’s own. The nature of the eye is to look not at
itself but at other things; and therefore to observe and blame
faults in another is a very suitable way of becoming con-
scious of one’s own. We require a looking-glass for the due
dressing of our morals.
The same rule applies in the case of style and fine writing.
If, instead of condemning, you applaud some new folly in
these matters, you will imitate it. That is just why literary
follies have such vogue in Germany. The Germans are a very
tolerant people—everybody can see that! Their maxim is—
Hanc veniam damns petimusque vicissim.
69
Schopenhauer
SECTION 32. When he is young, a man of noble character
fancies that the relations prevailing amongst mankind, and
the alliances to which these relations lead, are at bottom and
essentially, ideal in their nature; that is to say, that they rest
upon similarity of disposition or sentiment, or taste, or in-
tellectual power, and so on.
But, later on, he finds out that it is a real foundation which
underlies these alliances; that they are based upon some ma-
terial interest. This is the true foundation of almost all alli-
ances: nay, most men have no notion of an alliance resting
upon any other basis. Accordingly we find that a man is al-
ways measured by the office he holds, or by his occupation,
nationality, or family relations—in a word, by the position
and character which have been assigned him in the conven-
tional arrangements of life, where he is ticketed and treated
as so much goods. Reference to what he is in himself, as a
man—to the measure of his own personal qualities—is never
made unless for convenience’ sake: and so that view of a
man is something exceptional, to be set aside and ignored,
the moment that anyone finds it disagreeable; and this is
what usually happens. But the more of personal worth a man
has, the less pleasure he will take in these conventional ar-
rangements; and he will try to withdraw from the sphere in
which they apply. The reason why these arrangements exist
at all, is simply that in this world of ours misery and need are
the chief features: therefore it is everywhere the essential and
paramount business of life to devise the means of alleviating
them.
70
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 33. As paper-money circulates in the world in-
stead of real coin, so, is the place of true esteem and genuine
friendship, you have the outward appearance of it—a mimic
show made to look as much like the real thing as possible.
On the other hand, it may be asked whether there are any
people who really deserve the true coin. For my own part, I
should certainly pay more respect to an honest dog wagging
his tail than to a hundred such demonstrations of human
regard.
True and genuine friendship presupposes a strong sympa-
thy with the weal and woe of another—purely objective in
its character and quite disinterested; and this in its turn means
an absolute identification of self with the object of friend-
ship. The egoism of human nature is so strongly antagonis-
tic to any such sympathy, that true friendship belongs to
that class of things—the sea-serpent, for instance,—with
regard to which no one knows whether they are fabulous or
really exist somewhere or other.
Still, in many cases, there is a grain of true and genuine
friendship in the relation of man to man, though generally,
of course, some secret personal interest is at the bottom of
them—some one among the many forms that selfishness can
take. But in a world where all is imperfect, this grain of true
feeling is such an ennobling influence that it gives some war-
rant for calling those relations by the name of friendship, for
they stand far above the ordinary friendships that prevail
amongst mankind. The latter are so constituted that, were
you to hear how your dear friends speak of you behind your
back, you would never say another word to them.
Apart from the case where it would be a real help to you if
your friend were to make some great sacrifice to serve you,
there is no better means of testing the genuineness of his
feelings than the way in which he receives the news of a mis-
fortune that has just happened to you. At that moment the
expression of his features will either show that his one thought
is that of true and sincere sympathy for you; or else the abso-
lute composure of his countenance, or the passing trace of
something other than sympathy, will confirm the well-known
maxim of La Rochefoucauld: Dans l’adversite de nos meilleurs
amis, nous trouvons toujours quelque chose qui ne nous deplait
pas. Indeed, at such a moment, the ordinary so-called friend
will find it hard to suppress the signs of a slight smile of
71
Schopenhauer
pleasure. There are few ways by which you can make more
certain of putting people into a good humor than by telling
them of some trouble that has recently befallen you, or by
unreservedly disclosing some personal weakness of yours.
How characteristic this is of humanity!
Distance and long absence are always prejudicial to friend-
ship, however disinclined a man may be to admit. Our re-
gard for people whom we do not see—even though they be
our dearest friends—gradually dries up in the course of years,
and they become abstract notions; so that our interest in
them grows to be more and more intellectual,—nay, it is
kept up only as a kind of tradition; whilst we retain a lively
and deep interest in those who are constantly before our eyes,
even if they be only pet animals. This shows how much men
are limited by their senses, and how true is the remark that
Goethe makes in Tasso about the dominant influence of the
present moment:—
Die Gegenwart ist eine mächtige Göttin1
1 Act iv., se. 4.
Friends of the house are very rightly so called; because they
are friends of the house rather than of its master; in other
words, they are more like cats than dogs.
Your friends will tell you that they are sincere; your en-
emies are really so. Let your enemies’ censure be like a bitter
medicine, to be used as a means of self-knowledge.
A friend in need, as the saying goes, is rare. Nay, it is just
the contrary; no sooner have you made a friend than he is in
need, and asks for a loan.
72
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 34. A man must be still a greenhorn in the ways
of the world, if he imagines that he can make himself popu-
lar in society by exhibiting intelligence and discernment. With
the immense majority of people, such qualities excite hatred
and resentment, which are rendered all the harder to bear by
the fact that people are obliged to suppress—even from them-
selves—the real reason of their anger.
What actually takes place is this. A man feels and perceives
that the person with whom he is conversing is intellectually
very much his superior.
1
He thereupon secretly and half unconsciously concludes that
his interlocutor must form a proportionately low and limited
estimate of his abilities. That is a method of reasoning—an
enthymeme—which rouses the bitterest feelings of sullen and
rancorous hatred. And so Gracian is quite right in saying that
the only way to win affection from people is to show the most
animal-like simplicity of demeanor—para ser bien quisto, el
unico medio vestirse la piel del mas simple de los brutos.
1
To show your intelligence and discernment is only an in-
direct way of reproaching other people for being dull and
incapable. And besides, it is natural for a vulgar man to be
violently agitated by the sight of opposition in any form;
and in this case envy comes in as the secret cause of his hos-
tility. For it is a matter of daily observation that people take
the greatest pleasure in that which satisfies their vanity; and
vanity cannot be satisfied without comparison with others.
Now, there is nothing of which a man is prouder than of
intellectual ability, for it is this that gives him his command-
1 Cf. Welt als Wills und Vorstellung, Bk. II. p. 256 (4th Edit.),
where I quote from Dr. Johnson, and from Merck, the friend
of Goethe’s youth. The former says: There is nothing by which
a man exasperates most people more, than by displaying a supe-
rior ability of brilliancy in conversation. They seem pleased at
the time, but their envy makes them curse him at their hearts.
(Boswells Life of Johnson aetat: 74).
1 Translator’s Note.—Balthazar Graeian, Oraculo manual, y arte
de prudencia, 240. Gracian (1584-1658) was a Spanish prose
writer and Jesuit, whose works deal chiefly with the observa-
tion of character in the various phenomena of life.
Schopenhauer, among others, had a great admiration for his
worldly philosophy, and translated his Oraculo manual—a
system of rules for the conduct of life—into German. The
same book was translated into English towards the close of
the seventeenth century.
73
Schopenhauer
ing place in the animal world. It is an exceedingly rash thing
to let any one see that you are decidedly superior to him in
this respect, and to let other people see it too; because he will
then thirst for vengeance, and generally look about for an
opportunity of taking it by means of insult, because this is to
pass from the sphere of intellect to that of will—and there,
all are on an equal footing as regards the feeling of hostility.
Hence, while rank and riches may always reckon upon def-
erential treatment in society, that is something which intel-
lectual ability can never expect; to be ignored is the greatest
favor shown to it; and if people notice it at all, it is because
they regard it as a piece of impertinence, or else as some-
thing to which its possessor has no legitimate right, and upon
which he dares to pride himself; and in retaliation and re-
venge for his conduct, people secretly try and humiliate him
in some other way; and if they wait to do this, it is only for a
fitting opportunity. A man may be as humble as possible in
his demeanor, and yet hardly ever get people to overlook his
crime in standing intellectually above them. In the Garden
of Roses, Sadi makes the remark:—You should know that fool-
ish people are a hundredfold more averse to meeting the wise
than the wise are indisposed for the company of the foolish.
On the other hand, it is a real recommendation to be stu-
pid. For just as warmth is agreeable to the body, so it does
the mind good to feel its superiority; and a man will seek
company likely to give him this feeling, as instinctively as he
will approach the fireplace or walk in the sun if he wants to
get warm. But this means that he will be disliked on account
of his superiority; and if a man is to be liked, he must really
be inferior in point of intellect; and the same thing holds
good of a woman in point of beauty. To give proof of real
and unfeigned inferiority to some of the people you meet—
that is a very difficult business indeed!
Consider how kindly and heartily a girl who is passably
pretty will welcome one who is downright ugly. Physical ad-
vantages are not thought so much of in the case of man,
though I suppose you would rather a little man sat next to
you than one who was bigger than yourself. This is why,
amongst men, it is the dull and ignorant, and amongst
women, the ugly, who are always popular and in request.
1
It
1 If you desire to get on in the world, friends and acquain-
tances are by far the best passport to fortune. The possession
74
Essays – Volume One
is likely to be said of such people that they are extremely
good-natured, because every one wants to find a pretext for
caring about them—a pretext which will blind both himself
and other people to the real reason why he likes them. This
is also why mental superiority of any sort always tends to
isolate its possessor; people run away from him out of pure
hatred, and say all manner of bad things about him by way
of justifying their action. Beauty, in the case of women, has
a similar effect: very pretty girls have no friends of their own
sex, and they even find it hard to get another girl to keep
them company. A handsome woman should always avoid
applying for a position as companion, because the moment
she enters the room, her prospective mistress will scowl at
her beauty, as a piece of folly with which, both for her own
and for her daughter’s sake, she can very well dispense. But if
the girl has advantages of rank, the case is very different;
because rank, unlike personal qualities which work by the
force of mere contrast, produces its effect by a process of
reflection; much in the same way as the particular hue of a
person’s complexion depends upon the prevailing tone of his
immediate surroundings.
of a great deal of ability makes a man proud, and therefore
not apt to flatter those who have very little, and from whom,
on that account, the possession of great ability should be
carefully concealed. The consciousness of small intellectual
power has just the opposite effect, and is very compatible
with a humble, affable and companionable nature, and with
respect for what is mean and wretched. This is why an infe-
rior sort of man has so many friends to befriend and encour-
age him.
These remarks are applicable not only to advancement in
political life, but to all competition for places of honor and
dignity, nay, even for reputation in the world of science, lit-
erature and art. In learned societies, for example, medioc-
rity—that very acceptable quality—is always to the fore,
whilst merit meets with tardy recognition, or with none at
all. So it is in everything.
75
Schopenhauer
SECTION 35. Our trust in other people often consists in
great measure of pure laziness, selfishness and vanity on our
own part: I say laziness, because, instead of making inquiries
ourselves, and exercising an active care, we prefer to trust
others; selfishness, because we are led to confide in people by
the pressure of our own affairs; and vanity, when we ask con-
fidence for a matter on which we rather pride ourselves. And
yet, for all that, we expect people to be true to the trust we
repose in them.
But we ought not to become angry if people put no trust
in us: because that really means that they pay honesty the
sincere compliment of regarding it as a very rare thing,—so
rare, indeed, as to leave us in doubt whether its existence is
not merely fabulous.
SECTION 36. Politeness,—which the Chinese hold to be a
cardinal virtue,—is based upon two considerations of policy.
I have explained one of these considerations in my Ethics;
the other is as follows:—Politeness is a tacit agreement that
people’s miserable defects, whether moral or intellectual, shall
on either side be ignored and not made the subject of re-
proach; and since these defects are thus rendered somewhat
less obtrusive, the result is mutually advantageous.
1
It is a wise thing to be polite; consequently, it is a stupid
thing to be rude. To make enemies by unnecessary and will-
ful incivility, is just as insane a proceeding as to set your
house on fire. For politeness is like a counter—an avowedly
1 Translator’s Note.—In the passage referred to (Grundlage
der Moral, collected works, Vol. IV., pp. 187 and 198),
Schopenhauer explains politeness as a conventional and sys-
tematic attempt to mask the egoism of human nature in the
small affairs of life,—an egoism so repulsive that some such
device is necessary for the purpose of concealing its ugliness.
The relation which politeness bears to the true love of one’s
neighbor is analogous to that existing between justice as an
affair of legality, and justice as the real integrity of the heart.
76
Essays – Volume One
false coin, with which it is foolish to be stingy. A sensible
man will be generous in the use of it. It is customary in every
country to end a letter with the words:—your most obedient
servant—votre très-humble serviteur—suo devotissimo servo.
(The Germans are the only people who suppress the word
servant—Diener—because, of course, it is not true!) How-
ever, to carry politeness to such an extent as to damage your
prospects, is like giving money where only counters are ex-
pected.
Wax, a substance naturally hard and brittle, can be made
soft by the application of a little warmth, so that it will take
any shape you please. In the same way, by being polite and
friendly, you can make people pliable and obliging, even
though they are apt to be crabbed and malevolent. Hence
politeness is to human nature what warmth is to wax.
Of course, it is no easy matter to be polite; in so far, I
mean, as it requires us to show great respect for everybody,
whereas most people deserve none at all; and again in so far
as it demands that we should feign the most lively interest in
people, when we must be very glad that we have nothing to
do with them. To combine politeness with pride is a master-
piece of wisdom.
We should be much less ready to lose our temper over an
insult,—which, in the strict sense of the word, means that
we have not been treated with respect,—if, on the one hand,
we have not such an exaggerated estimate of our value and
dignity—that is to say, if we were not so immensely proud
of ourselves; and, on the other hand, if we had arrived at any
clear notion of the judgment which, in his heart, one man
generally passes upon another. If most people resent the slight-
est hint that any blame attaches to them, you may imagine
their feelings if they were to overhear what their acquain-
tance say about them. You should never lose sight of the fact
that ordinary politeness is only a grinning mask: if it shifts
its place a little, or is removed for a moment, there is no use
raising a hue and cry. When a man is downright rude, it is as
though he had taken off all his clothes, and stood before you
in puris naturalibus. Like most men in this condition, he
does not present a very attractive appearance.
77
Schopenhauer
SECTION 37. You ought never to take any man as a model
for what you should do or leave undone; because position
and circumstances are in no two cases alike, and difference
of character gives a peculiar, individual tone to what a man
does. Hence duo cum faciunt idem, non est idem—two per-
sons may do the same thing with a different result. A man
should act in accordance with his own character, as soon as
he has carefully deliberated on what he is about to do.
The outcome of this is that originality cannot be dispensed
with in practical matters: otherwise, what a man does will
not accord with what he is.
SECTION 38. Never combat any man’s opinion; for though
you reached the age of Methuselah, you would never have
done setting him right upon all the absurd things that he
believes.
It is also well to avoid correcting people’s mistakes in con-
versation, however good your intentions may be; for it is
easy to offend people, and difficult, if not impossible, to mend
them.
If you feel irritated by the absurd remarks of two people
whose conversation you happen to overhear, you should
imagine that you are listening to a dialogue of two fools in a
comedy. Probatum est.
The man who comes into the world with the notion that
he is really going to instruct in matters of the highest impor-
tance, may thank his stars if he escapes with a whole skin.
78
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 39. If you want your judgment to be accepted,
express it coolly and without passion. All violence has its
seat in the will; and so, if your judgment is expressed with
vehemence, people will consider it an effort of will, and
not the outcome of knowledge, which is in its nature cold
and unimpassioned. Since the will is the primary and radi-
cal element in human nature, and intellect merely super-
venes as something secondary, people are more likely to
believe that the opinion you express with so much vehe-
mence is due to the excited state of your will, rather than
that the excitement of the will comes only from the ardent
nature of your opinion.
SECTION 40. Even when you are fully justified in praising
yourself, you should never be seduced into doing so. For
vanity is so very common, and merit so very uncommon,
that even if a man appears to be praising himself, though
very indirectly, people will be ready to lay a hundred to one
that he is talking out of pure vanity, and that he has not
sense enough to see what a fool he is making of himself.
Still, for all that, there may be some truth in Bacon’s re-
mark that, as in the case of calumny, if you throw enough
dirt, some of it will stick, so it it also in regard to self-praise;
with the conclusion that self-praise, in small doses, is to be
recommended.
1
1Translator’s Note.—Schopenhauer alludes to the following
passage in Bacon’s De Augmentis Scientiarum, Bk. viii., ch. 2:
Sicut enim dici solet de calumnia, audacter calumniare, sem-
per aliquid haeret; sic dici potest de jactantia, (nisi plane
deformis fuerit et ridicula), audacter te vendita, semper aliquid
haeret. Haerebit certe apud populum, licet prudentiores
subrideant. Itaque existimatio parta apud plurimos paucorum
fastidium abunde compensabit.
79
Schopenhauer
SECTION 41. If you have reason to suspect that a person is
telling you a lie, look as though you believed every word he
said. This will give him courage to go on; he will become
more vehement in his assertions, and in the end betray him-
self.
Again, if you perceive that a person is trying to conceal
something from you, but with only partial success, look as
though you did not believe him, This opposition on your
part will provoke him into leading out his reserve of truth
and bringing the whole force of it to bear upon your incre-
dulity.
SECTION 42. You should regard all your private affairs as
secrets, and, in respect of them, treat your acquaintances,
even though you are on good terms with them, as perfect
strangers, letting them know nothing more than they can
see for themselves. For in course of time, and under altered
circumstances, you may find it a disadvantage that they know
even the most harmless things about you.
And, as a general rule, it is more advisable to show your
intelligence by saying nothing than by speaking out; for si-
lence is a matter of prudence, whilst speech has something
in it of vanity. The opportunities for displaying the one or
the other quality occur equally often; but the fleeting satis-
faction afforded by speech is often preferred to the perma-
nent advantage secured by silence.
The feeling of relief which lively people experience in speak-
ing aloud when no one is listening, should not be indulged,
lest it grow into a habit; for in this way thought establishes
such very friendly terms with speech, that conversation is
apt to become a process of thinking aloud. Prudence exacts
that a wide gulf should be fixed between what we think and
what we say.
80
Essays – Volume One
At times we fancy that people are utterly unable to believe
in the truth of some statement affecting us personally, whereas
it never occurs to them to doubt it; but if we give them the
slightest opportunity of doubting it, they find it absolutely
impossible to believe it any more. We often betray ourselves
into revealing something, simply because we suppose that
people cannot help noticing it,—just as a man will throw
himself down from a great height because he loses his head,
in other words, because he fancies that he cannot retain a
firm footing any longer; the torment of his position is so
great, that he thinks it better to put an end to it at once. This
is the kind of insanity which is called acrophobia.
But it should not be forgotten how clever people are in
regard to affairs which do not concern them, even though
they show no particularly sign of acuteness in other matters.
This is a kind of algebra in which people are very proficient:
give them a single fact to go upon, and they will solve the
most complicated problems. So, if you wish to relate some
event that happened long ago, without mentioning any
names, or otherwise indicating the persons to whom you
refer, you should be very careful not to introduce into your
narrative anything that might point, however distantly, to
some definite fact, whether it is a particular locality, or a
date, or the name of some one who was only to a small ex-
tent implicated, or anything else that was even remotely con-
nected with the event; for that at once gives people some-
thing positive to go upon, and by the aid of their talent for
this sort of algebra, they will discover all the rest. Their curi-
osity in these matters becomes a kind of enthusiasm: their
will spurs on their intellect, and drives it forward to the at-
tainment of the most remote results. For however
unsusceptible and different people may be to general and
universal truths, they are very ardent in the matter of par-
ticular details.
In keeping with what I have said, it will be found that all
those who profess to give instructions in the wisdom of life
are specially urgent in commending the practice of silence,
and assign manifold reasons why it should be observed; so it
is not necessary for me to enlarge upon the subject any fur-
ther. However, I may just add one or two little known Ara-
bian proverbs, which occur to me as peculiarly appropriate:—
Do not tell a friend anything that you would conceal from an
81
Schopenhauer
enemy.
A secret is in my custody, if I keep it; but should it escape me,
it is I who am the prisoner.
The tree of silence bears the fruit of peace.
SECTION 43. Money is never spent to so much advantage
as when you have been cheated out of it; for at one stroke
you have purchased prudence.
82
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 44. If possible, no animosity should be felt for
anyone. But carefully observe and remember the manner in
which a man conducts himself, so that you may take the
measure of his value,—at any rate in regard to yourself,—
and regulate your bearing towards him accordingly; never
losing sight of the fact that character is unalterable, and that
to forget the bad features in a man’s disposition is like throw-
ing away hard-won money. Thus you will protect yourself
against the results of unwise intimacy and foolish friend-
ship.
Give way neither to love nor to hate, is one-half of worldly
wisdom: say nothing and believe nothing, the other half. Truly,
a world where there is need of such rules as this and the
following, is one upon which a man may well turn his back.
SECTION 45. To speak angrily to a person, to show your
hatred by what you say or by the way you look, is an unnec-
essary proceeding—dangerous, foolish, ridiculous, and vul-
gar.
Anger and hatred should never be shown otherwise than
in what you do; and feelings will be all the more effective in
action, in so far as you avoid the exhibition of them in any
other way. It is only cold-blooded animals whose bite is poi-
sonous.
83
Schopenhauer
SECTION 46. To speak without emphasizing your words—
parler sans accent—is an old rule with those who are wise in
the world’s ways. It means that you should leave other people
to discover what it is that you have said; and as their minds
are slow, you can make your escape in time. On the other
hand, to emphasize your meaning—parler avec accent—is to
address their feelings; and the result is always the opposite of
what you expect. If you are polite enough in your manner
and courteous in your tone there are many people whom
you may abuse outright, and yet run no immediate risk of
offending them.
CHAPTER IV
CHAPTER IV
CHAPTER IV
CHAPTER IV
CHAPTER IV
W
W
W
W
WORLDL
ORLDL
ORLDL
ORLDL
ORLDLY FOR
Y FOR
Y FOR
Y FOR
Y FORTUNE.—SECTION 47.
TUNE.—SECTION 47.
TUNE.—SECTION 47.
TUNE.—SECTION 47.
TUNE.—SECTION 47.
H
OWEVER
VARIED
THE
FORMS
that human destiny may take,
the same elements are always present; and so life is every-
where much of a piece, whether it passed in the cottage or in
the palace, in the barrack or in the cloister. Alter the circum-
stance as much as you please! point to strange adventures,
successes, failures! life is like a sweet-shop, where there is a
great variety of things, odd in shape and diverse in color—
one and all made from the same paste. And when men speak
of some one’s success, the lot of the man who has failed is
not so very different as it seems. The inequalities in the world
are like the combinations in a kaleidoscope; at every turn a
fresh picture strikes the eye; and yet, in reality, you see only
the same bits of glass as you saw before.
84
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 48. An ancient writer says, very truly, that there
are three great powers in the world; Sagacity, Strength, and
Luck,—[Greek: sunetos, kratos, tuchu.] I think the last is
the most efficacious.
A man’s life is like the voyage of a ship, where luck—se-
cunda aut adversa fortuna—acts the part of the wind, and
speeds the vessel on its way or drives it far out of its course.
All that the man can do for himself is of little avail; like the
rudder, which, if worked hard and continuously, may help
in the navigation of the ship; and yet all may be lost again by
a sudden squall. But if the wind is only in the right quarter,
the ship will sail on so as not to need any steering. The power
of luck is nowhere better expressed than in a certain Spanish
proverb: Da Ventura a tu hijo, y echa lo en el mar—give your
son luck and throw him into the sea.
Still, chance, it may be said, is a malignant power, and as
little as possible should be left to its agency. And yet where is
there any giver who, in dispensing gifts, tells us quite clearly
that we have no right to them, and that we owe them not to
any merit on our part, but wholly to the goodness and grace
of the giver—at the same time allowing us to cherish the
joyful hope of receiving, in all humility, further undeserved
gifts from the same hands—where is there any giver like that,
unless it be Chance? who understands the kingly art of show-
ing the recipient that all merit is powerless and unavailing
against the royal grace and favor.
On looking back over the course of his life,—that labyrin-
thine way of error,—a man must see many points where luck
failed him and misfortune came; and then it is easy to carry
self-reproach to an unjust excess. For the course of a man’s
life is in no wise entirely of his own making; it is the product
of two factors—the series of things that happened, and his
own resolves in regard to them, and these two are constantly
interacting upon and modifying each other. And besides
these, another influence is at work in the very limited extent
of a man’s horizon, whether it is that he cannot see very far
ahead in respect of the plans he will adopt, or that he is still
less able to predict the course of future events: his knowl-
edge is strictly confined to present plans and present events.
Hence, as long as a man’s goal is far off, he cannot steer straight
for it; he must be content to make a course that is approxi-
mately right; and in following the direction in which he thinks
85
Schopenhauer
he ought to go, he will often have occasion to tack.
All that a man can do is to form such resolves as from time
to time accord with the circumstances in which he is placed,
in the hope of thus managing to advance a step nearer to-
wards the final goal. It is usually the case that the position in
which we stand, and the object at which we aim, resemble
two tendencies working with dissimilar strength in different
directions; and the course of our life is represented by their
diagonal, or resultant force.
Terence makes the remark that life is like a game at dice,
where if the number that turns up is not precisely the one
you want, you can still contrive to use it equally:—in vita est
hominum quasi cum ludas tesseris; si illud quod maxime opus
est jactu non cadit, illud quod cecidit forte, id arte ut corrigas.
1
Or, to put the matter more shortly, life is a game of cards,
when the cards are shuffled and dealt by fate. But for my
present purpose, the most suitable simile would be that of a
game of chess, where the plan we determined to follow is
conditioned by the play of our rival,—in life, by the caprice
of fate. We are compelled to modify our tactics, often to
such an extent that, as we carry them out, hardly a single
feature of the original plan can be recognized.
But above and beyond all this, there is another influence
that makes itself felt in our lives. It is a trite saying—only
too frequently true—that we are often more foolish than we
think. On the other hand, we are often wiser than we fancy
ourselves to be. This, however, is a discovery which only those
can make, of whom it is really true; and it takes them a long
time to make it. Our brains are not the wisest part of us. In
the great moments of life, when a man decides upon an im-
portant step, his action is directed not so much by any clear
knowledge of the right thing to do, as by an inner impulse—
you may almost call it an instinct—proceeding from the
deepest foundations of his being. If, later on, he attempts to
criticise his action by the light of hard and fast ideas of what
is right in the abstract—those unprofitable ideas which are
learnt by rote, or, it may be, borrowed from other people; if
he begins to apply general rules, the principles which have
guided others, to his own case, without sufficiently weigh-
ing the maxim that one man’s meat is another’s poison, then
1 He seems to have been referring to a game something like
backgammon.
86
Essays – Volume One
he will run great risk of doing himself an injustice. The re-
sult will show where the right course lay. It is only when a
man has reached the happy age of wisdom that he is capable
of just judgment in regard either to his own actions or to
those of others.
It may be that this impulse or instinct is the unconscious
effect of a kind of prophetic dream which is forgotten when
we awake—lending our life a uniformity of tone, a dramatic
unity, such as could never result from the unstable moments
of consciousness, when we are so easily led into error, so
liable to strike a false note. It is in virtue of some such pro-
phetic dream that a man feels himself called to great achieve-
ments in a special sphere, and works in that direction from
his youth up out of an inner and secret feeling that that is his
true path, just as by a similar instinct the bee is led to build
up its cells in the comb. This is the impulse which Balthazar
Gracian calls la gran sindéresis
1
—the great power of moral
discernment: it is something that a man instinctively feels to
be his salvation without which he were lost.
To act in accordance with abstract principles is a difficult
matter, and a great deal of practice will be required before
you can be even occasionally successful; it of tens happens
that the principles do not fit in with your particular case.
But every man has certain innate concrete principles—a part,
1Translator’s Note.—This obscure word appears to be derived
from the Greek sugtaereo (N.T. and Polyb.) meaning “to ob-
serve strictly.” It occurs in The Doctor and Student, a series of
dialogues between a doctor of divinity and a student on the
laws of England, first published in 1518; and is there (Dia-
log. I. ch. 13) explained as “a natural power of the soule, set
in the highest part thereof, moving and stirring it to good,
and abhoring evil.” This passage is copied into Milton’s Com-
monplace Book, edit. Horwood, § 79. The word is also found
in the Dictionary of the Spanish Academy (vol. vi. of the
year 1739) in the sense of an innate discernment of moral
principles, where a quotation is given from Madre Maria de
Jesus, abbess of the convent of the Conception at Agreda, a
mystical writer of the seventeenth century, frequently con-
sulted by Philip IV.,—and again in the Bolognese Dictio-
nary of 1824, with a similar meaning, illustrated from the
writings of Salvini (1653-1729). For these references I am
indebted to the kindness of Mr. Norman Maccoll.
87
Schopenhauer
as it were, of the very blood that flows in his veins, the sum
or result, in fact, of all his thoughts, feelings and volitions.
Usually he has no knowledge of them in any abstract form;
it is only when he looks back upon the course his life has
taken, that he becomes aware of having been always led on
by them—as though they formed an invisible clue which he
had followed unawares.
SECTION 49. That Time works great changes, and that all
things are in their nature fleeting—these are truths that should
never be forgotten. Hence, in whatever case you may be, it is
well to picture to yourself the opposite: in prosperity, to be
mindful of misfortune; in friendship, of enmity; in good
weather, of days when the sky is overcast; in love, of hatred;
in moments of trust, to imagine the betrayal that will make
you regret your confidence; and so, too, when you are in evil
plight, to have a lively sense of happier times—what a last-
ing source of true worldly wisdom were there! We should
then always reflect, and not be so very easily deceived; be-
cause, in general, we should anticipate the very changes that
the years will bring.
Perhaps in no form of knowledge is personal experience so
indispensable as in learning to see that all things are unstable
and transitory in this world. There is nothing that, in its
own place and for the time it lasts, is not a product of neces-
sity, and therefore capable of being fully justified; and it is
this fact that makes circumstances of every year, every month,
even of every day, seem as though they might maintain their
right to last to all eternity. But we know that this can never
88
Essays – Volume One
be the case, and that in a world where all is fleeting, change
alone endures. He is a prudent man who is not only unde-
ceived by apparent stability, but is able to forecast the lines
upon which movement will take place.
1
But people generally think that present circumstances will
last, and that matters will go on in the future as they have
clone in the past. Their mistakes arises from the fact that
they do not understand the cause of the things they see—
causes which, unlike the effects they produce, contain in
themselves the germ of future change. The effects are all that
people know, and they hold fast to them on the supposition
that those unknown causes, which were sufficient to bring
them about, will also be able to maintain them as they are.
This is a very common error; and the fact that it is common
is not without its advantage, for it means that people always
err in unison; and hence the calamity which results from the
error affects all alike, and is therefore easy to bear; whereas, if
a philosopher makes a mistake, he is alone in his error, and
so at a double disadvantage.
1
But in saying that we should anticipate the effects of time,
I mean that we should mentally forecast what they are likely
to be; I do not mean that we should practically forestall them,
by demanding the immediate performance of promises which
time alone can fulfill. The man who makes his demand will
find out that there is no worse or more exacting usurer than
Time; and that, if you compel Time to give money in ad-
1Chance plays so great a part in all human affairs that when
a man tries to ward off a remote danger by present sacrifice,
the danger often vanishes under some new and unforeseen
development of events; and then the sacrifice, in addition to
being a complete loss, brings about such an altered state of
things as to be in itself a source of positive danger in the face
of this new development. In taking measures of precaution,
then, it is well not to look too far ahead, but to reckon with
chance; and often to oppose a courageous front to a danger,
in the hope that, like many a dark thunder-cloud, it may
pass away without breaking.
1 I may remark, parenthetically, that all this is a confirma-
tion of the principle laid down in Die Welt als Wille und
Vorstellung (Bk. I. p. 94: 4th edit.), that error always consists
in making a wrong inference, that is, in ascribing a given ef-
fect to something that did not cause it.
89
Schopenhauer
vance, you will have to pay a rate of interest more ruinous
than any Jew would require. It is possible, for instance, to
make a tree burst forth into leaf, blossom, or even bear fruit
within a few days, by the application of unslaked lime and
artificial heat; but after that the tree will wither away. So a
young man may abuse his strength—it may be only for a
few weeks—by trying to do at nineteen what he could easily
manage at thirty, and Time may give him the loan for which
he asks; but the interest he will have to pay comes out of the
strength of his later years; nay, it is part of his very life itself.
There are some kinds of illness in which entire restoration
to health is possible only by letting the complaint run its
natural course; after which it disappears without leaving any
trace of its existence. But if the sufferer is very impatient,
and, while he is still affected, insists that he is completely
well, in this case, too, Time will grant the loan, and the com-
plaint may be shaken off; but life-long weakness and chronic
mischief will be the interest paid upon it.
Again, in time of war or general disturbance, a man may
require ready money at once, and have to sell out his invest-
ments in land or consols for a third or even a still smaller
fraction of the sum he would have received from them, if he
could have waited for the market to right itself, which would
have happened in due course; but he compels Time to grant
him a loan, and his loss is the interest he has to pay. Or
perhaps he wants to go on a long journey and requires the
money: in one or two years he could lay by a sufficient sum
out of his income, but he cannot afford to wait; and so he
either borrows it or deducts it from his capital; in other words,
he gets Time to lend him the money in advance. The inter-
est he pays is a disordered state of his accounts, and perma-
nent and increasing deficits, which he can never make good.
Such is Time’s usury; and all who cannot wait are its vic-
tims. There is no more thriftless proceeding than to try and
mend the measured pace of Time. Be careful, then, not to
become its debtor.
90
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 50. In the daily affairs of life, you will have very
many opportunities of recognizing a characteristic difference
between ordinary people of prudence and discretion. In esti-
mating the possibility of danger in connection with any un-
dertaking, an ordinary man will confine his inquiries to the
kind of risk that has already attended such undertakings in
the past; whereas a prudent person will look ahead, and con-
sider everything that might possibly happen in the future,
having regard to a certain Spanish maxim: lo que no acaece en
un ano, acaece en un rato—a thing may not happen in a year,
and yet may happen within two minutes.
The difference in question is, of course, quite natural; for
it requires some amount of discernment to calculate possi-
bilities; but a man need only have his senses about him to
see what has already happened.
Do not omit to sacrifice to evil spirits. What I mean is,
that a man should not hesitate about spending time, trouble,
and money, or giving up his comfort, or restricting his aims
and denying himself, if he can thereby shut the door on the
possibility of misfortune. The most terrible misfortunes are
also the most improbable and remote—the least likely to
occur. The rule I am giving is best exemplified in the prac-
tice of insurance,—a public sacrifice made on the altar of
anxiety. Therefore take out your policy of insurance!
91
Schopenhauer
SECTION 51. Whatever fate befalls you, do not give way
to great rejoicings or great lamentations; partly because all
things are full of change, and your fortune may turn at any
moment; partly because men are so apt to be deceived in
their judgment as to what is good or bad for them.
Almost every one in his turn has lamented over something
which afterwards turned out to be the very best thing for
him that could have happened—or rejoiced at an event which
became the source of his greatest sufferings. The right state
of mind has been finely portrayed by Shakespeare:
I have felt so many quirks of joy and grief That the first face of
neither, on the start, Can woman me unto’t.
1
And, in general, it may be said that, if a man takes misfor-
tunes quietly, it is because he knows that very many dreadful
things may happen in the course of life; and so he looks
upon the trouble of the moment as only a very small part of
that which might come. This is the Stoic temper—never to
be unmindful of the sad fate of humanity—condicionis
humanoe oblitus; but always to remember that our existence
is full of woe and misery: and that the ills to which we are
exposed are innumerable. Wherever he be, a man need only
cast a look around, to revive the sense of human misery:
there before his eyes he can see mankind struggling and floun-
dering in torment,—all for the sake of a wretched existence,
barren and unprofitable!
If he remembers this, a man will not expect very much
from life, but learn to accommodate himself to a world where
all is relative and no perfect state exists;—always looking mis-
fortune in the face, and if he cannot avoid it, meeting it with
courage.
It should never be forgotten that misfortune, be it great or
small, is the element in which we live. But that is no reason
why a man should indulge in fretful complaints, and, like
Beresford,
1
pull a long face over the Miseries of Human Life,—
and not a single hour is free from them; or still less, call
upon the Deity at every flea-bite—in pulicis morsu Deum
1 All’s Well that Ends Well, Act. ii. Sc. 2.
1Translator’s Note.—Rev. James Beresford (1764-1840), mis-
cellaneous writer. The full title of this, his chief work, is “The
Miseries of Human Life; or the last groans of Timothy Testy
and Samuel Sensitive, with a few supplementary sighs from
Mrs. Testy.”
92
Essays – Volume One
invocare. Our aim should be to look well about us, to ward
off misfortune by going to meet it, to attain such perfection
and refinement in averting the disagreeable things of life,—
whether they come from our fellow-men or from the physi-
cal world,—that, like a clever fox, we may slip out of the
way of every mishap, great or small; remembering that a
mishap is generally only our own awkwardness in disguise.
The main reason why misfortune falls less heavily upon
us, if we have looked upon its occurrence as not impossible,
and, as the saying is, prepared ourselves for it, may be this:
if, before this misfortune comes, we have quietly thought
over it as something which may or may not happen, the whole
of its extent and range is known to us, and we can, at least,
determine how far it will affect us; so that, if it really arrives,
it does not depress us unduly—its weight is not felt to be
greater than it actually is. But if no preparation has been
made to meet it, and it comes unexpectedly, the mind is in a
state of terror for the moment and unable to measure the
full extent of the calamity; it seems so far-reaching in its ef-
fects that the victim might well think there was no limit to
them; in any case, its range is exaggerated. In the same way,
darkness and uncertainty always increase the sense of dan-
ger. And, of course, if we have thought over the possibility of
misfortune, we have also at the same time considered the
sources to which we shall look for help and consolation; or,
at any rate, we have accustomed ourselves to the idea of it.
There is nothing that better fits us to endure the misfor-
tunes of life with composure, than to know for certain that
everything that happens—from the smallest up to the greatest
facts of existence—happens of necessity.
1
A man soon accom-
modates himself to the inevitable—to something that must
be; and if he knows that nothing can happen except of ne-
cessity, he will see that things cannot be other that they
are, and that even the strangest chances in the world are just
as much a product of necessity as phenomena which obey
well-known rules and turn out exactly in accordance with
expectation. Let me here refer to what I have said elsewhere
on the soothing effect of the knowledge that all things are
1 This is a truth which I have firmly established in my prize-
essay on the Freedom of the Will, where the reader will find a
detailed explanation of the grounds on which it rests. Cf. espe-
cially p. 60. [Schopenhauer’s Works, 4th Edit., vol. iv.—Tr.]
93
Schopenhauer
inevitable and a product of necessity.
1
If a man is steeped in the knowledge of this truth, he will,
first of all, do what he can, and then readily endure what he
must.
We may regard the petty vexations of life that are con-
stantly happening, as designed to keep us in practice for bear-
ing great misfortunes, so that we may not become completely
enervated by a career of prosperity. A man should be as
Siegfried, armed cap-à-pie, towards the small troubles of ev-
ery day—those little differences we have with our fellow-
men, insignificant disputes, unbecoming conduct in other
people, petty gossip, and many other similar annoyances of
life; he should not feel them at all, much less take them to
heart and brood over them, but hold them at arm’s length
and push them out of his way, like stones that lie in the road,
and upon no account think about them and give them a
place in his reflections.
SECTION 52. What people commonly call Fate is, as a gen-
eral rule, nothing but their own stupid and foolish conduct.
There is a fine passage in Homer,
1
illustrating the truth of
this remark, where the poet praises [GREEK: maetis]—
shrewd council; and his advice is worthy of all attention. For
if wickedness is atoned for only in another world, stupidity
gets its reward here—although, now and then, mercy may
be shown to the offender.
It is not ferocity but cunning that strikes fear into the heart
and forebodes danger; so true it is that the human brain is a
more terrible weapon than the lion’s paw.
The most finished man of the world would be one who
was never irresolute and never in a hurry.
1 Cf. Welt als Wille und Vorstellung, Bk. I. p. 361 (4th edit.).
1 Iliad, xxiii. 313, sqq.
94
Essays – Volume One
SECTION 53. Courage comes next to prudence as a quality
of mind very essential to happiness. It is quite true that no
one can endow himself with either, since a man inherits pru-
dence from his mother and courage from his father; still, if
he has these qualities, he can do much to develop them by
means of resolute exercise.
In this world, where the game is played with loaded dice, a
man must have a temper of iron, with armor proof to the
blows of fate, and weapons to make his way against men.
Life is one long battle; we have to fight at every step; and
Voltaire very rightly says that if we succeed, it is at the point
of the sword, and that we die with the weapon in our hand—
on ne réussit dans ce monde qua la pointe de l’épee, et on meurt
les armes à la main. It is a cowardly soul that shrinks or grows
faint and despondent as soon as the storm begins to gather,
or even when the first cloud appears on the horizon. Our
motto should be No Surrender; and far from yielding to the
ills of life, let us take fresh courage from misfortune:—
Tu ne cede malis sed contra audentior ito.
1
1Virgil, Aeneid, vi. 95.
As long as the issue of any matter fraught with peril is still in
doubt, and there is yet some possibility left that all may come
right, no one should ever tremble or think of anything but
resistance,—just as a man should not despair of the weather
if he can see a bit of blue sky anywhere. Let our attitude be
such that we should not quake even if the world fell in ruins
about us:—
Si fractus illabatur orbis
Impavidum ferient ruinae.
1
Our whole life itself—let alone its blessings—would not
be worth such a cowardly trembling and shrinking of the
heart. Therefore, let us face life courageously and show a
firm front to every ill:—
Quocirca vivite fortes Fortiaque adversis opponite
pectora rebus.
Still, it is possible for courage to be carried to an excess and
1Horace, Odes iii. 3.
95
Schopenhauer
to degenerate into rashness. It may even be said that some
amount of fear is necessary, if we are to exist at all in the
world, and cowardice is only the exaggerated form of it. This
truth has been very well expressed by Bacon, in his account
of Terror Panicus; and the etymological account which he
gives of its meaning, is very superior to the ancient explana-
tion preserved for us by Plutarch.
1
He connects the expres-
sion with Pan the personification of Nature;
2
and observes
that fear is innate in every living thing, and, in fact, tends to
its preservation, but that it is apt to come into play without
due cause, and that man is especially exposed to it. The chief
feature of this Panie Terror is that there is no clear notion of
any definite danger bound up with it; that it presumes rather
than knows that danger exists; and that, in case of need, it
pleads fright itself as the reason for being afraid.
1De Iside et Osiride ch. 14.
2De Sapientia Veterum, C. 6. Natura enim rerum omnibus
viventibus indidit mentum ac formidinem, vitae atque essentiae
suae conservatricem, ac mala ingruentia vitantem et depellentem.
Verumtamen eaden natura modum tenere nescia est: sed
timoribus salutaribus semper vanos et innanes admiscet; adeo
ut omnia (si intus conspici darentur) Panicis terroribus
plenissima sint praesertim humana.
CHAPTER
CHAPTER
CHAPTER
CHAPTER
CHAPTER V
V
V
V
V
THE A
THE A
THE A
THE A
THE AGES OF LIFE
GES OF LIFE
GES OF LIFE
GES OF LIFE
GES OF LIFE
T
HERE
IS
A
VERY
FINE
SAYING
of Voltaire’s to the effect that
every age of life has its own peculiar mental character, and
that a man will feel completely unhappy if his mind is not in
accordance with his years:—
Qui n’a pas l’esprit de son âge,
De son âge atout le malheur.
It will, therefore, be a fitting close to our speculations upon
the nature of happiness, if we glance at the chances which
the various periods of life produce in us.
Our whole life long it is the present, and the present alone,
that we actually possess: the only difference is that at the
beginning of life we look forward to a long future, and that
towards the end we look back upon a long past; also that our
temperament, but not our character, undergoes certain well-
known changes, which make the present wear a different color
96
Essays – Volume One
at each period of life.
I have elsewhere stated that in childhood we are more given
to using our intellect than our will; and I have explained why
this is so.
1
It is just for this reason that the first quarter of life
is so happy: as we look back upon it in after years, it seems a
sort of lost paradise. In childhood our relations with others
are limited, our wants are few,—in a word, there is little stimu-
lus for the will; and so our chief concern is the extension of
our knowledge. The intellect—like the brain, which attains
its full size in the seventh year,
2
is developed early, though it
takes time to mature; and it explores the whole world of its
surroundings in its constant search for nutriment: it is then
that existence is in itself an ever fresh delight, and all things
sparkle with the charm of novelty.
This is why the years of childhood are like a long poem.
For the function of poetry, as of all art, is to grasp the Idea—
in the Platonic sense; in other words, to apprehend a par-
ticular object in such a way as to perceive its essential nature,
the characteristics it has in common with all other objects of
the same kind; so that a single object appears as the repre-
sentative of a class, and the results of one experience hold
good for a thousand.
It may be thought that my remarks are opposed to fact,
and that the child is never occupied with anything beyond
the individual objects or events which are presented to it
from time to time, and then only in so far as they interest
and excite its will for the moment; but this is not really the
case. In those early years, life—in the full meaning of the
word, is something so new and fresh, and its sensations are
so keen and unblunted by repetition, that, in the midst of all
its pursuits and without any clear consciousness of what it is
doing, the child is always silently occupied in grasping the
nature of life itself,—in arriving at its fundamental character
1 Translator’s Note.—Schopenhauer refers to Die Welt als Wille
und Vorstellung, Bk. II. c, 31, p. 451 (4th edit.), where he
explains that this is due to the fact that at that period of life
the brain and nervous system are much more developed than
any other part of the organism.
2 Translator’s Note.—This statement is not quite correct. The
weight of the brain increases rapidly up to the seventh year,
more slowly between the sixteenth and the twentieth year,
still more slowly till between thirty and forty years of age,
when it attains its maximum. At each decennial period after
this, it is supposed to decrease in weight on the average, an
ounce for every ten years.
97
Schopenhauer
and general outline by means of separate scenes and experi-
ences; or, to use Spinoza’s phraseology, the child is learning
to see the things and persons about it sub specie aeternitatis,—
as particular manifestations of universal law.
The younger we are, then, the more does every individual
object represent for us the whole class to which it belongs;
but as the years increase, this becomes less and less the case.
That is the reason why youthful impressions are so different
from those of old age. And that it also why the slight knowl-
edge and experience gained in childhood and youth after-
wards come to stand as the permanent rubric, or heading,
for all the knowledge acquired in later life,—those early forms
of knowledge passing into categories, as it were, under which
the results of subsequent experience are classified; though a
clear consciousness of what is being done, does not always
attend upon the process.
In this way the earliest years of a man’s life lay the founda-
tion of his view of the world, whether it be shallow or deep;
and although this view may be extended and perfected later
on, it is not materially altered. It is an effect of this purely
objective and therefore poetical view of the world,—essen-
tial to the period of childhood and promoted by the as yet
undeveloped state of the volitional energy—that, as children,
we are concerned much more with the acquisition of pure
knowledge than with exercising the power of will. Hence
that grave, fixed look observable in so many children, of which
Raphael makes such a happy use in his depiction of cherubs,
especially in the picture of the Sistine Madonna. The years of
childhood are thus rendered so full of bliss that the memory
of them is always coupled with longing and regret.
While we thus eagerly apply ourselves to learning the out-
ward aspect of things, as the primitive method of under-
standing the objects about us, education aims at instilling
into us ideas. But ideas furnish no information as to the real
and essential nature of objects, which, as the foundation and
true content of all knowledge, can be reached only by the
process called intuition. This is a kind of knowledge which
can in no wise be instilled into us from without; we must
arrive at it by and for ourselves.
Hence a man’s intellectual as well as his moral qualities
proceed from the depths of his own nature, and are not the
result of external influences; and no educational scheme—
98
Essays – Volume One
of Pestalozzi, or of any one else—can turn a born simpleton
into a man of sense. The thing is impossible! He was born a
simpleton, and a simpleton he will die.
It is the depth and intensity of this early intuitive knowl-
edge of the external world that explain why the experiences
of childhood take such a firm hold on the memory. When
we were young, we were completely absorbed in our imme-
diate surroundings; there was nothing to distract our atten-
tion from them; we looked upon the objects about us as
though they were the only ones of their kind, as though,
indeed, nothing else existed at all. Later on, when we come
to find out how many things there are in the world, this
primitive state of mind vanishes, and with it our patience.
I have said elsewhere
1
that the world, considered as ob-
ject,—in other words, as it is presented to us objectively,—
wears in general a pleasing aspect; but that in the world,
considered as subject,—that is, in regard to its inner nature,
which is will,—pain and trouble predominate. I may be al-
lowed to express the matter, briefly, thus: the world is glorious
to look at, but dreadful in reality.
Accordingly, we find that, in the years of childhood, the
world is much better known to us on its outer or objective
side, namely, as the presentation of will, than on the side of
its inner nature, namely, as the will itself. Since the objective
side wears a pleasing aspect, and the inner or subjective side,
with its tale of horror, remains as yet unknown, the youth, as
his intelligence develops, takes all the forms of beauty that
he sees, in nature and in art, for so many objects of blissful
existence; they are so beautiful to the outward eye that, on
their inner side, they must, he thinks, be much more beauti-
ful still. So the world lies before him like another Eden; and
this is the Arcadia in which we are all born.
A little later, this state of mind gives birth to a thirst for
real life—the impulse to do and suffer—which drives a man
forth into the hurly-burly of the world. There he learns the
other side of existence—the inner side, the will, which is
thwarted at every step. Then comes the great period of disil-
lusion, a period of very gradual growth; but once it has fairly
begun, a man will tell you that he has got over all his false
notions—l’âge des illusions est passé; and yet the process is
1 Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung, Bk. II. c. 31, p. 426-7
(4th Edit.), to which the reader is referred for a detailed ex-
planation of my meaning.
99
Schopenhauer
only beginning, and it goes on extending its sway and apply-
ing more and more to the whole of life.
So it may be said that in childhood, life looks like the scen-
ery in a theatre, as you view it from a distance; and that in
old age it is like the same scenery when you come up quite
close to it.
And, lastly, there is another circumstance that contributes
to the happiness of childhood. As spring commences, the
young leaves on the trees are similar in color and much the
same in shape; and in the first years of life we all resemble
one another and harmonize very well. But with puberty di-
vergence begins; and, like the radii of a circle, we go further
and further apart.
The period of youth, which forms the remainder of this
earlier half of our existence—and how many advantages it
has over the later half!—is troubled and made miserable by
the pursuit of happiness, as though there were no doubt that
it can be met with somewhere in life,—a hope that always
ends in failure and leads to discontent. An illusory image of
some vague future bliss—born of a dream and shaped by
fancy—floats before our eyes; and we search for the reality
in vain. So it is that the young man is generally dissatisfied
with the position in which he finds himself, whatever it may
be; he ascribes his disappointment solely to the state of things
that meets him on his first introduction to life, when he had
expected something very different; whereas it is only the van-
ity and wretchedness of human life everywhere that he is
now for the first time experiencing.
It would be a great advantage to a young man if his early
training could eradicate the idea that the world has a great
deal to offer him. But the usual result of education is to
strengthen this delusion; and our first ideas of life are gener-
ally taken from fiction rather than from fact.
In the bright dawn of our youthful days, the poetry of life
spreads out a gorgeous vision before us, and we torture our-
selves by longing to see it realized. We might as well wish to
grasp the rainbow! The youth expects his career to be like an
interesting romance; and there lies the germ of that disap-
pointment which I have been describing.
1
What lends a
charm to all these visions is just the fact that they are vision-
ary and not real, and that in contemplating them we are in
1 Cf. loc. cit., p. 428.
100
Essays – Volume One
the sphere of pure knowledge, which is sufficient in itself
and free from the noise and struggle of life. To try and realize
those visions is to make them an object of will—a process
which always involves pain.
2
If the chief feature of the earlier half of life is a never-satis-
fied longing after happiness, the later half is characterized by
the dread of misfortune. For, as we advance in years, it be-
comes in a greater or less degree clear that all happiness is
chimerical in its nature, and that pain alone is real. Accord-
ingly, in later years, we, or, at least, the more prudent amongst
us, are more intent upon eliminating what is painful from
our lives and making our position secure, than on the pur-
suit of positive pleasure. I may observe, by the way, that in
old age, we are better able to prevent misfortunes from com-
ing, and in youth better able to bear them when they come.
In my young days, I was always pleased to hear a ring at
my door: ah! thought I, now for something pleasant. But in
later life my feelings on such occasions were rather akin to
dismay than to pleasure: heaven help me! thought I, what
am I to do? A similar revulsion of feeling in regard to the
world of men takes place in all persons of any talent or dis-
tinction. For that very reason they cannot be said properly
to belong to the world; in a greater or less degree, according
to the extent of their superiority, they stand alone. In their
youth they have a sense of being abandoned by the world;
but later on, they feel as though they had escaped it. The
earlier feeling is an unpleasant one, and rests upon ignorance;
the second is pleasurable—for in the meantime they have
come to know what the world is.
The consequence of this is that, as compared with the ear-
lier, the later half of life, like the second part of a musical
period, has less of passionate longing and more restfulness
about it. And why is this the case Simply because, in youth,
a man fancies that there is a prodigious amount of happiness
and pleasure to be had in the world, only that it is difficult
to come by it; whereas, when he becomes old, he knows that
there is nothing of the kind; he makes his mind completely
at ease on the matter, enjoys the present hour as well as he
can, and even takes a pleasure in trifles.
The chief result gained by experience of life is clearness of
view. This is what distinguishes the man of mature age, and
2 Let me refer the reader, if he is interested in the subject, to
the volume already cited, chapter 37.
101
Schopenhauer
makes the world wear such a different aspect from that which
it presented in his youth or boyhood. It is only then that he
sees things quite plain, and takes them for that which they
really are: while in earlier years he saw a phantom-world, put
together out of the whims and crotchets of his own mind,
inherited prejudice and strange delusion: the real world was
hidden from him, or the vision of it distorted. The first thing
that experience finds to do is to free us from the phantoms
of the brain—those false notions that have been put into us
in youth.
To prevent their entrance at all would, of course, be the
best form of education, even though it were only negative in
aim: but it would be a task full of difficulty. At first the child’s
horizon would have to be limited as much as possible, and
yet within that limited sphere none but clear and correct
notions would have to be given; only after the child had
properly appreciated everything within it, might the sphere
be gradually enlarged; care being always taken that nothing
was left obscure, or half or wrongly understood. The conse-
quence of this training would be that the child’s notions of
men and things would always be limited and simple in their
character; but, on the other hand, they would be clear and
correct, and only need to be extended, not to be rectified.
The same line might be pursued on into the period of youth.
This method of education would lay special stress upon the
prohibition of novel reading; and the place of novels would
be taken by suitable biographical literature—the life of
Franklin, for instance, or Moritz’ Anton Reiser.
1
In our early days we fancy that the leading events in our
life, and the persons who are going to play an important part
in it, will make their entrance to the sound of drums and
trumpets; but when, in old age, we look back, we find that
they all came in quite quietly, slipped in, as it were, by the
side-door, almost unnoticed.
From the point of view we have been taking up until now,
life may be compared to a piece of embroidery, of which,
during the first half of his time, a man gets a sight of the
right side, and during the second half, of the wrong. The
wrong side is not so pretty as the right, but it is more in-
structive; it shows the way in which the threads have been
1 Translator’s Note.—Moritz was a miscellaneous writer of
the last century (1757-93). His Anton Reiser, composed in
the form of a novel, is practically an autobiography.
102
Essays – Volume One
worked together.
Intellectual superiority, even if it is of the highest kind,
will not secure for a man a preponderating place in conver-
sation until after he is forty years of age. For age and experi-
ence, though they can never be a substitute for intellectual
talent, may far outweigh it; and even in a person of the mean-
est capacity, they give a certain counterpoise to the power of
an extremely intellectual man, so long as the latter is young.
Of course I allude here to personal superiority, not to the
place a man may gain by his works.
And on passing his fortieth year, any man of the slightest
power of mind—any man, that is, who has more than the
sorry share of intellect with which Nature has endowed five-
sixths of mankind—will hardly fail to show some trace of
misanthropy. For, as is natural, he has by that time inferred
other people’s character from an examination of his own;
with the result that he has been gradually disappointed to
find that in the qualities of the head or in those of the heart—
and usually in both—he reaches a level to which they do not
attain; so he gladly avoids having anything more to do with
them. For it may be said, in general, that every man will love
or hate solitude—in other Words, his own society—just in
proportion as he is worth anything in himself. Kant has some
remarks upon this kind of misanthropy in his Critique of the
Faculty of Judgment.
1
In a young man, it is a bad sign, as well from an intellec-
tual as from a moral point of view, if he is precocious in
understanding the ways of the world, and in adapting him-
self to its pursuits; if he at once knows how to deal with
men, and enters upon life, as it were, fully prepared. It ar-
gues a vulgar nature. On the other hand, to be surprised and
astonished at the way people act, and to be clumsy and cross-
grained in having to do with them, indicates a character of
the nobler sort.
The cheerfulness and vivacity of youth are partly due to
the fact that, when we are ascending the hill of life, death is
not visible: it lies down at the bottom of the other side. But
once we have crossed the top of the hill, death comes in
view—death—which, until then, was known to us only by
hearsay. This makes our spirits droop, for at the same time
we begin to feel that our vital powers are on the ebb. A grave
1 Kritik der Urtheilskraft, Part I, §29, Note ad fin.
103
Schopenhauer
seriousness now takes the place of that early extravagance of
spirit; and the change is noticeable even in the expression of
a man’s face. As long as we are young, people may tell us
what they please! we look upon life as endless and use our
time recklessly; but the older we become, the more we prac-
tice economy. For towards the close of life, every day we live
gives us the same kind of sensation as the criminal experi-
ences at every step on his way to be tried.
From the standpoint of youth, life seems to stretch away
into an endless future; from the standpoint of old age, to go
back but a little way into the past; so that, at the beginning,
life presents us with a picture in which the objects appear a
great way off, as though we had reversed our telescope; while
in the end everything seems so close. To see how short life is,
a man must have grown old, that is to say, he must have
lived long.
On the other hand, as the years increase, things look smaller,
one and all; and Life, which had so firm and stable a base in
the days of our youth, now seems nothing but a rapid flight
of moments, every one of them illusory: we have come to see
that the whole world is vanity!
Time itself seems to go at a much slower pace when we are
young; so that not only is the first quarter of life the happi-
est, it is also the longest of all; it leaves more memories be-
hind it. If a man were put to it, he could tell you more out of
the first quarter of his life than out of two of the remaining
periods. Nay, in the spring of life, as in the spring of the year,
the days reach a length that is positively tiresome; but in the
autumn, whether of the year or of life, though they are short,
they are more genial and uniform.
But why is it that to an old man his past life appears so
short? For this reason: his memory is short; and so he fancies
that his life has been short too. He no longer remembers the
insignificant parts of it, and much that was unpleasant is
now forgotten; how little, then, there is left! For, in general,
a man’s memory is as imperfect as his intellect; and he must
make a practice of reflecting upon the lessons he has learned
and the events he has experienced, if he does not want them
both to sink gradually into the gulf of oblivion. Now, we are
unaccustomed to reflect upon matters of no importance, or,
as a rule, upon things that we have found disagreeable, and
yet that is necessary if the memory of them is to be pre-
104
Essays – Volume One
served. But the class of things that may be called insignifi-
cant is continually receiving fresh additions: much that wears
an air of importance at first, gradually becomes of no conse-
quence at all from the fact of its frequent repetition; so that
in the end we actually lose count of the number of times it
happens. Hence we are better able to remember the events
of our early than of our later years. The longer we live, the
fewer are the things that we can call important or significant
enough to deserve further consideration, and by this alone
can they be fixed in the memory; in other words, they are
forgotten as soon as they are past. Thus it is that time runs
on, leaving always fewer traces of its passage.
Further, if disagreeable things have happened to us, we do
not care to ruminate upon them, least of all when they touch
our vanity, as is usually the case; for few misfortunes fall upon
us for which we can be held entirely blameless. So people are
very ready to forget many things that are disagreeable, as
well as many that are unimportant.
It is from this double cause that our memory is so short;
and a man’s recollection of what has happened always be-
comes proportionately shorter, the more things that have
occupied him in life. The things we did in years gone by, the
events that happened long ago, are like those objects on the
coast which, to the seafarer on his outward voyage, become
smaller every minute, more unrecognizable and harder to
distinguish.
Again, it sometimes happens that memory and imagina-
tion will call up some long past scene as vividly as if it had
occurred only yesterday; so that the event in question seems
to stand very near to the present time. The reason of this is
that it is impossible to call up all the intervening period in
the same vivid way, as there is no one figure pervading it
which can be taken in at a glance; and besides, most of the
things that happened in that period are forgotten, and all
that remains of it is the general knowledge that we have lived
through it—a mere notion of abstract existence, not a direct
vision of some particular experience. It is this that causes
some single event of long ago to appear as though it took
place but yesterday: the intervening time vanishes, and the
whole of life looks incredibly short. Nay, there are occasional
moments in old age when we can scarcely believe that we are
so advanced in years, or that the long past lying behind us
105
Schopenhauer
has had any real existence—a feeling which is mainly due to
the circumstance that the present always seems fixed and
immovable as we look at it. These and similar mental phe-
nomena are ultimately to be traced to the fact that it is not
our nature in itself, but only the outward presentation of it,
that lies in time, and that the present is the point of contact
between the world as subject and the world as object.
1
Again, why is it that in youth we can see no end to the
years that seem to lie before us? Because we are obliged to
find room for all the things we hope to attain in life. We
cram the years so full of projects that if we were to try and
carry them all out, death would come prematurely though
we reached the age of Methuselah.
Another reason why life looks so long when we are young,
is that we are apt to measure its length by the few years we
have already lived. In those early years things are new to us,
and so they appear important; we dwell upon them after
they have happened and often call them to mind; and thus
in youth life seems replete with incident, and therefore of
long duration.
Sometimes we credit ourselves with a longing to be in some
distant spot, whereas, in truth, we are only longing to have the
time back again which we spent there—days when we were
younger and fresher than we are now. In those moments Time
mocks us by wearing the mask of space; and if we travel to the
spot, we can see how much we have been deceived.
There are two ways of reaching a great age, both of which
presuppose a sound constitution as a conditio sine quâ non.
They may be illustrated by two lamps, one of which burns a
long time with very little oil, because it has a very thin wick;
and the other just as long, though it has a very thick one,
because there is plenty of oil to feed it. Here, the oil is the
vital energy, and the difference in the wick is the manifold
way in which the vital energy is used.
Up to our thirty-sixth year, we may be compared, in re-
spect of the way in which we use our vital energy, to people
1 Translator’s Note.—By this remark Schopenhauer means
that will, which, as he argues, forms the inner reality under-
lying all the phenomena of life and nature, is not in itself
affected by time; but that, on the other hand, time is neces-
sary for the objectification of the will, for the will as pre-
sented in the passing phenomena of the world. Time is thus
definable as the condition of change, and the present time as
the only point of contact between reality and appearance.
106
Essays – Volume One
who live on the interest of their money: what they spend to-
day, they have again to-morrow. But from the age of thirty-
six onwards, our position is like that of the investor who
begins to entrench upon his capital. At first he hardly no-
tices any difference at all, as the greater part of his expenses
is covered by the interest of his securities; and if the deficit is
but slight, he pays no attention to it. But the deficit goes on
increasing, until he awakes to the fact that it is becoming
more serious every day: his position becomes less and less
secure, and he feels himself growing poorer and poorer, while
he has no expectation of this drain upon his resources com-
ing to an end. His fall from wealth to poverty becomes faster
every moment—like the fall of a solid body in space, until at
last he has absolutely nothing left. A man is truly in a woeful
plight if both the terms of this comparison—his vital energy
and his wealth—really begin to melt away at one and the
same time. It is the dread of this calamity that makes love of
possession increase with age.
On the other hand, at the beginning of life, in the years
before we attain majority, and for some little time after-
wards—the state of our vital energy puts us on a level with
those who each year lay by a part of their interest and add it
to their capital: in other words, not only does their interest
come in regularly, but the capital is constantly receiving ad-
ditions. This happy condition of affairs is sometimes brought
about—with health as with money—under the watchful care
of some honest guardian. O happy youth, and sad old age!
Nevertheless, a man should economize his strength even
when he is young. Aristotle
1
observes that amongst those
who were victors at Olympia only two or three gained a prize
at two different periods, once in boyhood and then again
when they came to be men; and the reason of this was that
the premature efforts which the training involved, so com-
pletely exhausted their powers that they failed to last on into
manhood. As this is true of muscular, so it is still more true
of nervous energy, of which all intellectual achievements are
the manifestation. Hence, those infant prodigies—ingenia
praecoda—the fruit of a hot-house education, who surprise
us by their cleverness as children, afterwards turn out very
ordinary folk. Nay, the manner in which boys are forced into
an early acquaintance with the ancient tongues may, per-
1 Politics.
107
Schopenhauer
haps, be to blame for the dullness and lack of judgment which
distinguish so many learned persons.
I have said that almost every man’s character seems to be
specially suited to some one period of life, so that on reach-
ing it the man is at his best. Some people are charming so
long as they are young, and afterwards there is nothing at-
tractive about them; others are vigorous and active in man-
hood, and then lose all the value they possess as they ad-
vance in years; many appear to best advantage in old age,
when their character assumes a gentler tone, as becomes men
who have seen the world and take life easily. This is often the
case with the French.
This peculiarity must be due to the fact that the man’s
character has something in it akin to the qualities of youth
or manhood or old age—something which accords with one
or another of these periods of life, or perhaps acts as a cor-
rective to its special failings.
The mariner observes the progress he makes only by the
way in which objects on the coast fade away into the dis-
tance and apparently decrease in size. In the same way a man
becomes conscious that he is advancing in years when he
finds that people older than himself begin to seem young to
him.
It has already been remarked that the older a man becomes,
the fewer are the traces left in his mind by all that he sees,
does or experiences, and the cause of this has been explained.
There is thus a sense in which it may be said that it is only in
youth that a man lives with a full degree of consciousness,
and that he is only half alive when he is old. As the years
advance, his consciousness of what goes on about him
dwindles, and the things of life hurry by without making
any impression upon him, just as none is made by a work of
art seen for the thousandth time. A man does what his hand
finds to do, and afterwards he does not know whether he has
done it or not.
As life becomes more and more unconscious, the nearer it
approaches the point at which all consciousness ceases, the
course of time itself seems to increase in rapidity. In child-
hood all the things and circumstances of life are novel; and
that is sufficient to awake us to the full consciousness of ex-
istence: hence, at that age, the day seems of such immense
length. The same thing happens when we are traveling: one
108
Essays – Volume One
month seems longer then than four spent at home. Still,
though time seems to last longer when we are young or on a
journey, the sense of novelty does not prevent it from now
and then in reality hanging heavily upon our hands under
both these circumstances, at any rate more than is the case
when we are old or staying at home. But the intellect gradu-
ally becomes so rubbed down and blunted by long habitua-
tion to such impressions that things have a constant ten-
dency to produce less and less impression upon us as they
pass by; and this makes time seem increasingly less impor-
tant, and therefore shorter in duration: the hours of the boy
are longer than the days of the old man. Accordingly, time
goes faster and faster the longer we live, like a ball rolling
down a hill. Or, to take another example: as in a revolving
disc, the further a point lies from the centre, the more rapid
is its rate of progression, so it is in the wheel of life; the
further you stand from the beginning, the faster time moves
for you. Hence it may be said that as far as concerns the
immediate sensation that time makes upon our minds, the
length of any given year is in direct proportion to the num-
ber of times it will divide our whole life: for instance, at the
age of fifty the year appears to us only one-tenth as long as it
did at the age of five.
This variation in the rate at which time appears to move,
exercises a most decided influence upon the whole nature of
our existence at every period of it. First of all, it causes child-
hood—even though it embrace only a span of fifteen years—
to seem the longest period of life, and therefore the richest
in reminiscences. Next, it brings it about that a man is apt to
be bored just in proportion as he is young. Consider, for
instance, that constant need of occupation—whether it is
work or play—that is shown by children: if they come to an
end of both work and play, a terrible feeling of boredom
ensues. Even in youth people are by no means free from this
tendency, and dread the hours when they have nothing to
do. As manhood approaches, boredom disappears; and old
men find the time too short when their days fly past them
like arrows from a bow. Of course, I must be understood to
speak of men, not of decrepit brutes. With this increased ra-
pidity of time, boredom mostly passes away as we advance
in life; and as the passions with all their attendant pain are
then laid asleep, the burden of life is, on the whole, appre-
109
Schopenhauer
ciably lighter in later years than in youth, provided, of course,
that health remains. So it is that the period immediately pre-
ceding the weakness and troubles of old age, receives the
name of a man’s best years.
That may be a true appellation, in view of the comfortable
feeling which those years bring; but for all that the years of
youth, when our consciousness is lively and open to every
sort of impression, have this privilege—that then the seeds
are sown and the buds come forth; it is the springtime of the
mind. Deep truths may be perceived, but can never be
excogitated—that is to say, the first knowledge of them is
immediate, called forth by some momentary impression. This
knowledge is of such a kind as to be attainable only when
the impressions are strong, lively and deep; and if we are to
be acquainted with deep truths, everything depends upon a
proper use of our early years. In later life, we may be better
able to work upon other people,—upon the world, because
our natures are then finished and rounded off, and no more
a prey to fresh views; but then the world is less able to work
upon us. These are the years of action and achievement; while
youth is the time for forming fundamental conceptions, and
laying down the ground-work of thought.
In youth it is the outward aspect of things that most en-
gages us; while in age, thought or reflection is the predomi-
nating quality of the mind. Hence, youth is the time for
poetry, and age is more inclined to philosophy. In practical
affairs it is the same: a man shapes his resolutions in youth
more by the impression that the outward world makes upon
him; whereas, when he is old, it is thought that determines
his actions. This is partly to be explained by the fact that it is
only when a man is old that the results of outward observa-
tion are present in sufficient numbers to allow of their being
classified according to the ideas they represent,—a process
which in its turn causes those ideas to be more fully under-
stood in all their bearings, and the exact value and amount
of trust to be placed in them, fixed and determined; while at
the same time he has grown accustomed to the impressions
produced by the various phenomena of life, and their effects
on him are no longer what they were. Contrarily, in youth,
the impressions that things make, that is to say, the outward
aspects of life, are so overpoweringly strong, especially in the
case of people of lively and imaginative disposition, that they
110
Essays – Volume One
view the world like a picture; and their chief concern is the
figure they cut in it, the appearance they present; nay, they
are unaware of the extent to which this is the case. It is a
quality of mind that shows itself—if in no other way—in
that personal vanity, and that love of fine clothes, which dis-
tinguish young people.
There can be no doubt that the intellectual powers are most
capable of enduring great and sustained efforts in youth, up
to the age of thirty-five at latest; from which period their
strength begins to decline, though very gradually. Still, the
later years of life, and even old age itself, are not without
their intellectual compensation. It is only then that a man
can be said to be really rich in experience or in learning; he
has then had time and opportunity enough to enable him to
see and think over life from all its sides; he has been able to
compare one thing with another, and to discover points of
contact and connecting links, so that only then are the true
relations of things rightly understood. Further, in old age
there comes an increased depth in the knowledge that was
acquired in youth; a man has now many more illustrations
of any ideas he may have attained; things which he thought
he knew when he was young, he now knows in reality. And
besides, his range of knowledge is wider; and in whatever
direction it extends, it is thorough, and therefore formed
into a consistent and connected whole; whereas in youth
knowledge is always defective and fragmentary.
A complete and adequate notion of life can never be at-
tained by any one who does not reach old age; for it is only
the old man who sees life whole and knows its natural course;
it is only he who is acquainted—and this is most impor-
tant—not only with its entrance, like the rest of mankind,
but with its exit too; so that he alone has a full sense of its
utter vanity; whilst the others never cease to labor under the
false notion that everything will come right in the end.
On the other hand, there is more conceptive power in
youth, and at that time of life a man can make more out of
the little that he knows. In age, judgment, penetration and
thoroughness predominate. Youth is the time for amassing
the material for a knowledge of the world that shall be dis-
tinctive and peculiar,—for an original view of life, in other
words, the legacy that a man of genius leaves to his fellow-
men; it is, however, only in later years that he becomes mas-
111
Schopenhauer
ter of his material. Accordingly it will be found that, as a
rule, a great writer gives his best work to the world when he
is about fifty years of age. But though the tree of knowledge
must reach its full height before it can bear fruit, the roots of
it lie in youth.
Every generation, no matter how paltry its character, thinks
itself much wiser than the one immediately preceding it, let
alone those that are more remote. It is just the same with the
different periods in a man’s life; and yet often, in the one
case no less than in the other, it is a mistaken opinion. In the
years of physical growth, when our powers of mind and our
stores of knowledge are receiving daily additions, it becomes
a habit for to-day to look down with contempt upon yester-
day. The habit strikes root, and remains even after the intel-
lectual powers have begun to decline,—when to-day should
rather look up with respect to yesterday. So it is that we of-
ten unduly depreciate the achievements as well as the judg-
ments of our youth. This seems the place for making the
general observation, that, although in its main qualities a
man’s intellect or head, as well as his character or heart, is
innate, yet the former is by no means so unalterable in its
nature as the latter. The fact is that the intellect is subject to
very many transformations, which, as a rule, do not fail to
make their actual appearance; and this is so, partly because
the intellect has a deep foundation in the physique, and partly
because the material with which it deals is given in experi-
ence. And so, from a physical point of view, we find that if a
man has any peculiar power, it first gradually increases in
strength until it reaches its acme, after which it enters upon
a path of slow decadence, until it ends in imbecility. But, on
the other hand, we must not lose sight of the fact that the
material which gives employment to a man’s powers and keeps
them in activity,—the subject-matter of thought and knowl-
edge, experience, intellectual attainments, the practice of see-
ing to the bottom of things, and so a perfect mental vision,
form in themselves a mass which continues to increase in
size, until the time comes when weakness shows itself, and
the man’s powers suddenly fail. The way in which these two
distinguishable elements combine in the same nature,—the
one absolutely unalterable, and the other subject to change
in two directions opposed to each other—explains the vari-
ety of mental attitude and the dissimilarity of value which
112
Essays – Volume One
attach to a man at different periods of life.
The same truth may be more broadly expressed by saying
that the first forty years of life furnish the text, while the
remaining thirty supply the commentary; and that without
the commentary we are unable to understand aright the true
sense and coherence of the text, together with the moral it
contains and all the subtle application of which it admits.
Towards the close of life, much the same thing happens as
at the end of a bal masqué—the masks are taken off. Then
you can see who the people really are, with whom you have
come into contact in your passage through the world. For by
the end of life characters have come out in their true light,
actions have borne fruit, achievements have been rightly ap-
preciated, and all shams have fallen to pieces. For this, Time
was in every case requisite.
But the most curious fact is that it is also only towards the
close of life than a man really recognizes and understands his
own true self,—the aims and objects he has followed in life,
more especially the kind of relation in which he has stood to
other people and to the world. It will often happen that as a
result of this knowledge, a man will have to assign himself a
lower place than he formerly thought was his due. But there
are exceptions to this rule; and it will occasionally be the
case that he will take a higher position than he had before.
This will be owing to the fact that he had no adequate no-
tion of the baseness of the world, and that he set up a higher
aim for himself than was followed by the rest of mankind.
The progress of life shows a man the stuff of which he is
made.
It is customary to call youth the happy, and age the sad
part of life. This would be true if it were the passions that
made a man happy. Youth is swayed to and fro by them; and
they give a great deal of pain and little pleasure. In age the
passions cool and leave a man at rest, and then forthwith his
mind takes a contemplative tone; the intellect is set free and
attains the upper hand. And since, in itself, intellect is be-
yond the range of pain, and man feels happy just in so far as
his intellect is the predominating part of him.
It need only be remembered that all pleasure is negative,
and that pain is positive in its nature, in order to see that the
passions can never be a source of happiness, and that age is
not the less to be envied on the ground that many pleasures
113
Schopenhauer
are denied it. For every sort of pleasure is never anything
more than the quietive of some need or longing; and that
pleasure should come to an end as soon as the need ceases, is
no more a subject of complaint than that a man cannot go
on eating after he has had his dinner, or fall asleep again
after a good night’s rest.
So far from youth being the happiest period of life, there is
much more truth in the remark made by Plato, at the begin-
ning of the Republic, that the prize should rather be given to
old age, because then at last a man is freed from the animal
passion which has hitherto never ceased to disquiet him. Nay,
it may even be said that the countless and manifold humors
which have their source in this passion, and the emotions
that spring from it, produce a mild state of madness; and
this lasts as long as the man is subject to the spell of the
impulse—this evil spirit, as it were, of which there is no rid-
dance—so that he never really becomes a reasonable being
until the passion is extinguished.
There is no doubt that, in general, and apart from indi-
vidual circumstances and particular dispositions, youth is
marked by a certain melancholy and sadness, while genial
sentiments attach to old age; and the reason for this is noth-
ing but the fact that the young man is still under the service,
nay, the forced labor, imposed by that evil spirit, which
scarcely ever leaves him a moment to himself. To this source
may be traced, directly or indirectly, almost all and every ill
that befalls or menaces mankind. The old man is genial and
cheerful because, after long lying in the bonds of passion, he
can now move about in freedom.
Still, it should not be forgotten that, when this passion is
extinguished, the true kernel of life is gone, and nothing
remains but the hollow shell; or, from another point of view,
life then becomes like a comedy, which, begun by real ac-
tors, is continued and brought to an end by automata dressed
in their clothes.
However that may be, youth is the period of unrest, and
age of repose; and from that very circumstance, the relative
degree of pleasure belonging to each may be inferred. The
child stretches out its little hands in the eager desire to seize
all the pretty things that meet its sight, charmed by the world
because all its senses are still so young and fresh. Much the
same thing happens with the youth, and he displays greater
114
Essays – Volume One
energy in his quest. He, too, is charmed by all the pretty
things and the many pleasing shapes that surround him; and
forthwith his imagination conjures up pleasures which the
world can never realize. So he is filled with an ardent desire
for he knows not what delights—robbing him of all rest and
making happiness impossible. But when old age is reached,
all this is over and done with, partly because the blood runs
cooler and the senses are no longer so easily allured; partly
because experience has shown the true value of things and
the futility of pleasure, whereby illusion has been gradually
dispelled, and the strange fancies and prejudices which pre-
viously concealed or distorted a free and true view of the
world, have been dissipated and put to flight; with the result
that a man can now get a juster and clearer view, and see
things as they are, and also in a measure attain more or less
insight into the nullity of all things on this earth.
It is this that gives almost every old man, no matter how
ordinary his faculties may be, a certain tincture of wisdom,
which distinguishes him from the young. But the chief re-
sult of all this change is the peace of mind that ensues—a
great element in happiness, and, in fact, the condition and
essence of it. While the young man fancies that there is a
vast amount of good things in the world, if he could only
come at them, the old man is steeped in the truth of the
Preacher’s words, that all things are vanity—knowing that,
however gilded the shell, the nut is hollow.
In these later years, and not before, a man comes to a true
appreciation of Horace’s maxim: Nil admirari. He is directly
and sincerely convinced of the vanity of everything and that
all the glories of the world are as nothing: his illusions are
gone. He is no more beset with the idea that there is any
particular amount of happiness anywhere, in the palace or
in the cottage, any more than he himself enjoys when he is
free from bodily or mental pain. The worldly distinctions of
great and small, high and low, exist for him no longer; and
in this blissful state of mind the old man may look down
with a smile upon all false notions. He is completely unde-
ceived, and knows that whatever may be done to adorn hu-
man life and deck it out in finery, its paltry character will
soon show through the glitter of its surroundings; and that,
paint and be jewel it as one may, it remains everywhere much
the same,—an existence which has no true value except in
115
Schopenhauer
freedom from pain, and is never to be estimated by the pres-
ence of pleasure, let alone, then, of display.
1
Disillusion is the chief characteristic of old age; for by that
time the fictions are gone which gave life its charm and
spurred on the mind to activity; the splendors of the world
have been proved null and vain; its pomp, grandeur and
magnificence are faded. A man has then found out that be-
hind most of the things he wants, and most of the pleasures
he longs for, there is very little after all; and so he comes by
degrees to see that our existence is all empty and void. It is
only when he is seventy years old that he quite understands
the first words of the Preacher; and this again explains why it
is that old men are sometimes fretful and morose.
It is often said that the common lot of old age is disease
and weariness of life. Disease is by no means essential to old
age; especially where a really long span of years is to be at-
tained; for as life goes on, the conditions of health and disor-
der tend to increase—crescente vita, crescit sanitas et morbus.
And as far as weariness or boredom is concerned, I have stated
above why old age is even less exposed to that form of evil
than youth. Nor is boredom by any means to be taken as a
necessary accompaniment of that solitude, which, for rea-
sons that do not require to be explained, old age certainly
cannot escape; it is rather the fate that awaits those who have
never known any other pleasures but the gratification of the
senses and the delights of society—who have left their minds
unenlightened and their faculties unused. It is quite true that
the intellectual faculties decline with the approach of old
age; but where they were originally strong, there will always
be enough left to combat the onslaught of boredom. And
then again, as I have said, experience, knowledge, reflection,
and skill in dealing with men, combine to give an old man
an increasingly accurate insight into the ways of the world;
his judgment becomes keen and he attains a coherent view
of life: his mental vision embraces a wider range. Constantly
finding new uses for his stores of knowledge and adding to
them at every opportunity, he maintains uninterrupted that
inward process of self-education, which gives employment
and satisfaction to the mind, and thus forms the due reward
of all its efforts.
All this serves in some measure as a compensation for de-
1 Cf. Horace, Epist. I. 12, I-4.
116
Essays – Volume One
creased intellectual power. And besides, Time, as I have re-
marked, seems to go much more quickly when we are ad-
vanced in years; and this is in itself a preventive of boredom.
There is no great harm in the fact that a man’s bodily strength
decreases in old age, unless, indeed, he requires it to make a
living. To be poor when one is old, is a great misfortune. If a
man is secure from that, and retains his health, old age may
be a very passable time of life. Its chief necessity is to be
comfortable and well off; and, in consequence, money is then
prized more than ever, because it is a substitute for failing
strength. Deserted by Venus, the old man likes to turn to
Bacchus to make him merry. In the place of wanting to see
things, to travel and learn, comes the desire to speak and
teach. It is a piece of good fortune if the old man retains
some of his love of study or of music or of the theatre,—if,
in general, he is still somewhat susceptible to the things about
him; as is, indeed, the case with some people to a very late
age. At that time of life, what a man has in himself is of greater
advantage to him that ever it was before.
There can be no doubt that most people who have never
been anything but dull and stupid, become more and more
of automata as they grow old. They have always thought,
said and done the same things as their neighbors; and noth-
ing that happens now can change their disposition, or make
them act otherwise. To talk to old people of this kind is like
writing on the sand; if you produce any impression at all, it
is gone almost immediately; old age is here nothing but the
caput mortuum of life—all that is essential to manhood is
gone. There are cases in which nature supplies a third set of
teeth in old age, thereby apparently demonstrating the fact
that that period of life is a second childhood.
It is certainly a very melancholy thing that all a man’s fac-
ulties tend to waste away as he grows old, and at a rate that
increases in rapidity: but still, this is a necessary, nay, a ben-
eficial arrangement, as otherwise death, for which it is a prepa-
ration, would be too hard to bear. So the greatest boon that
follows the attainment of extreme old age is euthanasia,—an
easy death, not ushered in by disease, and free from all pain
and struggle.
1
For let a man live as long as he may, he is
never conscious of any moment but the present, one and
1 See Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung, Bk. II. ch. 41, for
a further description of this happy end to life.
117
Schopenhauer
indivisible; and in those late years the mind loses more every
day by sheer forgetfulness than ever it gains anew.
The main difference between youth and age will always be
that youth looks forward to life, and old age to death; and
that while the one has a short past and a long future before
it, the case is just the opposite with the other. It is quite true
that when a man is old, to die is the only thing that awaits
him; while if he is young, he may expect to live; and the
question arises which of the two fates is the more hazardous,
and if life is not a matter which, on the whole, it is better to
have behind one than before? Does not the Preacher say: the
day of death [is better] than the day of one’s birth.
1
It is cer-
tainly a rash thing to wish for long life;
2
for as the Spanish
proverb has it, it means to see much evil,—Quien larga vida
vive mucho mal vide.
1 Ecclesiastes vii. 1.
2 The life of man cannot, strictly speaking, be called either
long or short, since it is the ultimate standard by which dura-
tion of time in regard to all other things is measured.
In one of the Vedic Upanishads (Oupnekhat, II.) the natu-
ral length of human life is put down at one hundred years.
And I believe this to be right. I have observed, as a matter of
fact, that it is only people who exceed the age of ninety who
attain euthanasia,—who die, that is to say, of no disease, apo-
plexy or convulsion, and pass away without agony of any
sort; nay, who sometimes even show no pallor, but expire
generally in a sitting attitude, and often after a meal,—or, I
may say, simply cease to live rather than die. To come to
one’s end before the age of ninety, means to die of disease, in
other words, prematurely.
Now the Old Testament (Psalms xc. 10) puts the limit of
human life at seventy, and if it is very long, at eighty years;
and what is more noticeable still, Herodotus (i. 32 and iii.
22) says the same thing. But this is wrong; and the error is
due simply to a rough and superficial estimate of the results
of daily experience. For if the natural length of life were from
seventy to eighty years, people would die, about that time,
of mere old age. Now this is certainly not the case. If they
die then, they die, like younger people, of disease; and disease
is something abnormal. Therefore it is not natural to die at
that age. It is only when they are between ninety and a hun-
dred that people die of old age; die, I mean, without suffer-
ing from any disease, or showing any special signs of their
condition, such as a struggle, death-rattle, convulsion, pal-
lor,—the absence of all which constitutes euthanasia. The
natural length of human life is a hundred years; and in as-
signing that limit the Upanishads are right once more.
118
Essays – Volume One
A man’s individual career is not, as Astrology wishes to
make out, to be predicted from observation of the planets;
but the course of human life in general, as far as the various
periods of it are concerned, may be likened to the succession
of the planets: so that we may be said to pass under the in-
fluence of each one of them in turn.
At ten, Mercury is in the ascendant; and at that age, a youth,
like this planet, is characterized by extreme mobility within
a narrow sphere, where trifles have a great effect upon him;
but under the guidance of so crafty and eloquent a god, he
easily makes great progress. Venus begins her sway during his
twentieth year, and then a man is wholly given up to the love
of women. At thirty, Mars comes to the front, and he is now
all energy and strength,—daring, pugnacious and arrogant.
When a man reaches the age of forty, he is under the rule
of the four Asteroids; that is to say, his life has gained some-
thing in extension. He is frugal; in other words, by the help
of Ceres, he favors what is useful; he has his own hearth, by
the influence of Vesta; Pallas has taught him that which is
necessary for him to know; and his wife—his Juno—rules as
the mistress of his house.
But at the age of fifty, Jupiter is the dominant influence. At
that period a man has outlived most of his contemporaries,
and he can feel himself superior to the generation about him.
He is still in the full enjoyment of his strength, and rich in
experience and knowledge; and if he has any power and po-
sition of his own, he is endowed with authority over all who
stand in his immediate surroundings. He is no more inclined
to receive orders from others; he wants to take command
himself. The work most suitable to him now is to guide and
rule within his own sphere. This is the point where Jupiter
culminates, and where the man of fifty years is at his best.
Then comes Saturn, at about the age of sixty, a weight as
of lead, dull and slow:—
But old folks, many feign as they were dead;
Unwieldy, slow, heavy and pale as lead.
Last of all, Uranus; or, as the saying is, a man goes to heaven.
I cannot find a place for Neptune, as this planet has been
very thoughtlessly named; because I may not call it as it should
be called—Eros. Otherwise I should point out how Begin-
119
Schopenhauer
ning and End meet together, and how closely and intimately
Eros is connected with Death: how Orcus, or Amenthes, as
the Egyptians called him, is not only the receiver but the
giver of all things—[Greek: lambanon kai didous]. Death is
the great reservoir of Life. Everything comes from Orcus;
everything that is alive now was once there. Could we but
understand the great trick by which that is done, all would
be clear!