INGOLD RESPONSE to critique

background image

http://journals.cambridge.org

Downloaded: 10 Nov 2010

IP address: 143.167.2.135

A response to my critics

31

Archaeological Dialogues 14 (1) 31–38 C

2007 Cambridge University Press

doi:10.1017/S1380203807002176 Printed in the United Kingdom

Writing texts, reading materials. A response to my critics
Tim Ingold

I would like to thank all four of my interlocutors for taking the trouble to
comment on my text, and for the clarity and cogency of their contributions.
They have forced me to think long and hard, and indeed to question my own
conclusions. For me at least, and I hope also for readers of Archaeological
dialogues
, this has been a debate worth having, and it has been going on as
much in my own mind as between myself and my critics. From the comments I
picked up seven lines of criticism to which I would like to offer some response.
They are: (i) that I have left the people out; (ii) that without a concept of
materiality one cannot address the social and historical significance of things
in people’s lives; (iii) that I am on the run from the contemporary world
of industrial artefacts and their consumers; (iv) that this escape is driven
by nostalgic yearning for the direct perception of an unsullied nature; (v)
that my depiction of material-culture studies is a caricature, in so far as
such studies have long recognized the entanglement of objects in networks
of relations; (vi) that my argument goes against the thinking of people in
many parts of the world who are preoccupied with materiality and the
possibilities of its transcendence; and (vii) that to emphasize materials in and
of themselves is a retrograde step that threatens to take us back to the tedious
enumeration of different kinds of stuff without regard to their meanings or
contexts of use. In what follows I shall tackle each of these criticisms in
turn.

To the first, I would respond that far from being absent from my account,

people are at the heart of it. They are there, carving wood and knapping
stone, making felt or spinning hair for tents, building and plastering houses,
preparing ink and parchment for writing, and so on. They are present,
however, in the same way that all living organisms are, as complex bundles
constituted by the flows and transformations of materials across the interface
between their bodily substances and the media that surround them. So when
Chris Tilley complains of the ‘virtual absence’ (p. 19) of people from my
discussion, or when Carl Knappett remarks that they ‘seem to take a back
seat’ (p. 23), it must be because they are looking for some superorganic
dimension by which the life of people exceeds their organic life. In classical
theory, of course, this dimension has been denoted by the word ‘social’. And,
sure enough, it is people’s social relations that are perceived to be missing.
To touch the stone on your desk as you sit alone in your study is, says
Knappett, ‘a rather asocial, solitary experiment’ (p. 21). By the same token,
presumably, touching another person would be deemed deeply social. Many
people would probably say the same about stroking their cat. But I am not
going to speculate on where to draw the line between a social relation with
another person and an asocial relation with a thing, because I do not believe
there is a line to be crossed. As I have argued elsewhere (Ingold 1997, 238), the
‘webs of significance’ in which persons are commonly said to be enmeshed are

background image

http://journals.cambridge.org

Downloaded: 10 Nov 2010

IP address: 143.167.2.135

32

discussion

not suspended above the paths they tread in their material lives but comprise
these very paths.

My critics are absolutely right to observe that the fate of the concept of

materiality is bound up with that of the social, and that by downplaying the
one – or even seeking its elimination – the other is also imperilled. Indeed the
habit of placing the word ‘social’ before ‘context’ entails a certain redundancy,
as does that of placing the word ‘material’ before ‘world’. Are there contexts
that are not social, or worlds that are not material? I was once discussing
the argument of this paper with a graduate student in archaeology who was
interested in the use of mud as a building material in ancient Egypt. ‘So’, I
said, ‘you are working on mud-bricks’. ‘No’, she responded very firmly, ‘I am
working on the materiality of brick’. Having read Tilley’s comment, I now
realize that in her response ‘the materiality of brick’ was actually a kind of
shorthand for ‘understanding brick in the social and historical context of the
use of mud by humans’. Just as the concept of the social is supposed to take
us beyond the existence and interactions of human beings as mere organisms,
so we need the concept of materiality, according to Tilley, in order to go
beyond ‘brute’ materials and their properties. Paradoxically, this leads him
simultaneously to advance and to counterpose two concepts of materiality:
the first referring to the physical world as it is given quite independently of
the presence, activities and purposes of humans; the second to the world as
it is caught up in these activities and lent significance by these purposes. ‘The
concept of materiality’, says Tilley, ‘is required because it tries to consider
and embrace subject–object relations going beyond the brute materiality of
stones’ (p. 17). Notice how, in this passage, the word ‘materiality’ appears
twice, with each of these contradictory meanings.

This argument reminds me of much older debates for and against the

human nature of human nature’, which likewise oscillated between a notion
of brute animality common to all creatures and one of an essential humanity
by which the social life of persons was thought to be raised onto a plane of
being over and above the purely biophysical (Eisenberg 1972; Ingold 1994,
19–25). In speaking of the world of materials rather than the material world,
my intent has been precisely to escape from this oscillation, both by returning
persons to where they belong, within the continuum of organic life, and by
recognizing that this life itself undergoes continual generation in currents
of materials. For Tilley, a stone can be treated as a lump of matter and
analysed for its physical properties, as by the geologist in his example, but
it has meaning and significance only in the context of human affairs. In the
world of materials, however, humans figure as much within the context for
stones as do stones within the context for humans. And these contexts, far
from lying on disparate levels of being, respectively social and natural, are
established as overlapping regions of the same world. It is not as though this
world were one of brute physicality, of mere matter, until people appeared
on the scene to give it meaning. Stones, too, have histories, forged in ongoing
relations with surroundings that may or may not include human beings and
much else besides. It is all very well to place stones within the context of
human social life and history, but within what context do we place this social
life and history if not the ever-unfolding world of materials in which the very

background image

http://journals.cambridge.org

Downloaded: 10 Nov 2010

IP address: 143.167.2.135

A response to my critics

33

being of humans, along with that of the non-humans they encounter, is bound
up?

To escape from the oscillation between the two materialities – the ‘brute’

materiality of non-human nature and the materiality that things acquire
from their insertion into the domain of human society – is not, then, to
regress from the latter to the former. Indeed Daniel Miller’s comment that
my argument reveals a streak of primitivism, or a yearning for a world in
which people would engage directly with ‘virgin materials’ as yet unsullied
by any processes of human industry (p. 26), perfectly exemplifies the illusion,
at the heart of material-culture studies, by which materials are contrived to
vanish, swallowed up by the objects made from them. The illusion tricks us
into thinking that materials can only exist in a raw, untransformed state,
since as soon as they are worked into artefacts they cannot be materials
any more. Most human beings alive today, Miller insists, ‘deal almost
entirely with artefacts far removed from any claim to be natural substances’
(p. 26). Thus we have to be concerned with the life histories not of wood
and stone, but of mobile phones, washing machines, tractors and so on.
Yet as I have pointed out, the naturalness or artificiality of things can never
be unequivocally determined, and in any case has not the slightest bearing
on the fact that these things are still made of materials. It is a matter of
opinion whether a child’s toy made of plastic is more ‘artificial’, on that
account, than one made of wood (Ingold 2000, 53). Plastic is a material
as much as stone is, and I could have exemplified my argument as well
with the one as with the other. This argument, to repeat, is that even when
materials are consolidated into the forms of artefacts, they are still there,
and continue to be caught up, along with their users, in the fluxes of the
medium.

It may be ‘blindingly obvious’ (p. 26), to Miller as to other students of

material culture, that in today’s world people deal with artefacts to an extent
that would have been unimaginable to our prehistoric forebears. But this
seems to have blinded them to what is equally obvious to people themselves,
namely that even as they go about their artefact-assisted lives they have to
contend with the elements. The householder worries about a leaky roof, rot in
his floorboards or the roots of trees threatening his foundations. The weather
forecast, broadcast on television, warns the motorist to beware of heavy rain,
fog or icy patches on roads. The holidaymaker purchases sunglasses and
lotion to protect her eyes and body from intense radiation. Is it primitivist
to acknowledge that we inhabit a world of earth, sky, wind and weather, in
which the sun shines, rain falls, trees grow and water can turn to ice? Life as
we know it depends on all these things. Throughout our lives we breathe the
air, more or less as we find it. I am not worried that it would be somehow
inauthentic if we ceased to do so. I am worried that we would all be dead. The
quality of the air is a matter of great concern to many people, especially as
industrial pollution tends to increase the incidence of respiratory disease. It is
something we have to deal with. Moreover, the more we deal with artefacts,
the more we have to contend with their wear and tear, brought about through
the reaction of the stuff they are made of with the materials with which they
come into contact. Thus the water pumped through a washing machine can

background image

http://journals.cambridge.org

Downloaded: 10 Nov 2010

IP address: 143.167.2.135

34

discussion

eventually cause the metal to rust, and the abrasion of earth and stones wears
down the hard rubber tyres of the tractor.

Once the maintenance and repair of artefacts becomes more trouble than

it is worth they are generally discarded, leaving a residue of materials that
we have still to deal with. I have no idea whether a hundred years from now
humans will still be using mobile phones. Perhaps by then they will have
been replaced by some other device, or perhaps we will have found ways to
live that do not depend on such a massive volume of remote communication.
What is certain, however, is that the heaps of plastic waste from millions of
discarded phones, contaminated by large concentrations of heavy metal, will
continue to blight the landscape in some parts of the world, posing a lasting
threat to human health. Compared to the duration of these heaps, the time
span of mobile phone communication will probably seem like a mere blip.
To make materials critical to understanding humanity, Miller claims, I would
have to return to the age of stone. I could, however, just as well travel to the
future, and imagine a world of materials left over after all the manufactured
artefacts of today have been thrown away. In short, to put materials first
is not to privilege the distant past over the immediate present, but to adopt
the perspective of the very long term. I entirely agree, with Bj ¨orn Nilsson,
that more than any other discipline, archaeology can offer such a perspective,
and for that reason I believe that archaeologists have a unique contribution
to make to understanding the world of materials. But I do not believe, as
Miller seems to, that ethnography is – by contrast to archaeology – tied to the
present. Ethnography is tied to people’s lives, and in life the past is continually
active in the present as it presses into the future.

If it is the perspective of the long term that brings materials and their

properties to light, so conversely a focus on the present, to the exclusion
of past and future, makes them disappear. In the extreme case such a focus
yields a snapshot of people ‘caught in the act’, as portrayed in the dioramas
of open-air museums. Nilsson tells us that the celebrated Swedish geographer
Torsten H ¨agerstrand favoured the diorama as a way of capturing a world
full of movement. Rather than being lined up in sequence on museum walls,
in the diorama artefacts could be placed in contexts of human use. The
waxwork blacksmith, for example, could be poised ready to strike with his
hammer at the forge. Yet in truth nothing in the diorama moves or breathes.
We see artefacts-in-context, a network of relations between a person – in
the figure of the blacksmith – and the things he uses. Such network images
have become commonplace in studies of material culture, and are nicely
epitomized by the logo for Material world, the new weblog for material-
and visual-culture studies (see www.materialworldblog.com), which shows a
number of medallions depicting commonplace objects (a book, a bicycle,
a bag, a boot, a bracelet and so on) connected up in a web of straight
lines. ‘Network thinking’, as Knappett suggests, ‘encourages a focus not
only on entities but also on connections’, making possible a ‘relational
perspective’ (p. 22). Miller, for his part, claims to have adopted a relational
perspective all along, and cannot see how the approach I advocate differs
from, or adds anything to, what he and his students have long been doing
already.

background image

http://journals.cambridge.org

Downloaded: 10 Nov 2010

IP address: 143.167.2.135

A response to my critics

35

Here is the difference. In place of the image of the network I suggest

that of a meshwork (Ingold 2006, 13–14). The meshwork consists not of
interconnected points but of interwoven lines. Every line is a relation, but the
relation is not between one thing and another – between, say, an artefact here
and a person there, or between one person or artefact and another. Rather,
the relation is a line along which materials flow, mix and mutate. Persons
and things, then, are formed in the meshwork as knots or bundles of such
relations. It is not, then, that things are entangled in relations; rather every
thing is itself an entanglement, and is thus linked to other things by way of
the flows of materials that make it up. So while the material world might be
depicted as it is in the weblog logo, as a network of interconnected objects, the
world of materials would be better described as a meshwork of interwoven
substances. This is what I had in mind when I wrote, for example, of the
multiple trails of growth and transformation that converge in the page of a
manuscript. And it is this meshwork that is covered up as soon as we treat
that manuscript page as a finished object in relation to other objects, rather
than as a bundle of materials whose constituent strands may be tied up with
other materials, in other bundles.

What of the criticism, then, that my thinking ignores ethnographic realities?

In ethnography, Miller writes, ‘one constantly comes across people who do
see the world in terms of immateriality and degrees of materiality’ (p. 25).
Such views are central to Hinduism and Buddhism, for example. I can claim
no expertise in the field of South Asian religion, and am therefore not qualified
to comment on whether ‘materiality’ has quite the same meaning in the
context of Hindu or Buddhist worship as it does in the anthropological
or archaeological study of material culture. I suspect not. Be that as it
may, I doubt whether even Miller would subscribe to such a thoroughgoing
theoretical relativism as would justify the use of any concept under the sun on
the grounds that it is an accepted part of the world view of the people studied.
My complaint, however, is that students of material culture have never come
clean about what they mean by materiality. Instead, they are tying themselves
up in semantic knots of the kind to which I have already drawn attention in
Tilley’s comment. But as scholars and academics, are we not all caught up in
semantics? This seems to be Miller’s point. My paper, he observes, ‘is actually
not a stone but a text’ (p. 25). As such it seeks to convey something about the
world by means of the written word. In writing the text I have therefore had
to confront the same issues of representation that other students of material
culture, whose stance I criticize, have had to grapple with. Perhaps, then, we
have more to say to one another than I let on.

Of course it is true that no academic writer can escape these issues.

However, my purpose in introducing the stone was not merely to offer apt
illustration of an argument that could have fared equally well without it. It
was rather part of a wider project, which presently guides my teaching as
well as my writing, to re-embed the practices of reading and writing, and
above all of thinking, within our observational engagements with the world
around us. I teach my students not only to think and write about what they
have observed, but also to observe thoughtfully and (particularly through
experiments in handwriting and drawing) to make the graphic act itself a

background image

http://journals.cambridge.org

Downloaded: 10 Nov 2010

IP address: 143.167.2.135

36

discussion

practice of observation. Thoughtful, writerly observation seems to me to lie
at the heart of good ethnography. Thus in my paper I wanted to demonstrate
that the world of materials is not only a world we can think about but one
that we can think with, or reciprocally, that is with us in our thoughts. I
began the paper with a reference to Henry Hodges’s Artefacts. Tilley recalls
how, as an undergraduate, having to read this book and others of its kind
almost led him to abandon the study of anthropology and archaeology. Why
did he find books like this so tedious? Because they were concerned only with
the properties of materials, in and for themselves. Lacking any concept of
materiality, they could not even begin to consider the meaning and significance
of these properties in the social and historical contexts of human lives. Having
no contexts in which to place his observations, Hodges’s book reads like a
compendium of pointless and irrelevant information. Is that really a beacon
for where I want anthropology and archaeology to go?

Of course not. But I would venture to suggest that if carpenters,

metalworkers and potters were required, as part of their training, to read
works in the tradition of material-culture studies, they would find them just
as tedious and irrelevant as Tilley found Artefacts to be to his training in an
academic discipline. Why? Because the interpretations they offer, of the social
meanings of things, are divorced from any practically grounded understanding
of materials and their properties. It is the same with a cookbook that – with
its endless lists of ingredients and quantities – would look dull and boring
on the scholar’s shelf, but in the kitchen could be a source of inspiration and
insight. Now I am not suggesting that we should all stop writing academic
texts and start producing the equivalent of cookbooks instead. I am rather
trying to find a way of moving beyond what I, and I think most students, find
to be a stifling division between academic study and observational practice.
I want to bring the two back together. Hence the stone. Miller is wrong to
assert that my paper – if by that is meant what I offer the reader – is not
a stone but a text. It is a stone with a text. The one is as much a part of it
as the other. Beginning and ending with the stone, the reading of the text is
deliberately framed within an observational practice. For, when all is said and
done, I believe our aim should be to read the world, not the texts that have
been written about it, and the purpose of written texts should be to enrich
our reading so that we might be better advised by, and responsive to, what is
going on there.

References

Allen, N.J., 1998: The category of substance. A Maussian theme revisited, in

W. James and N.J. Allen (eds), Marcel Mauss. A centenary tribute, New York,
175–91.

Banerjee, M., and D. Miller, 2003: The sari, Oxford.
Berggren,

Å

., and M. Burstr ¨om, 2002: Reflexiv f ¨altarkeologi?

Återsken av ett

seminarium

, Malm ¨o Kulturmilj ¨o and Riksantikvarie ¨ambetet, Malm ¨o and

Stockholm.

Bunn, S., 1997: Animal products, in P. Oliver (ed.), Encyclopedia of vernacular

architecture of the world, Vol. 1, Cambridge, 195–97.

background image

http://journals.cambridge.org

Downloaded: 10 Nov 2010

IP address: 143.167.2.135

A response to my critics

37

Charsley, S., 1982: Culture and sericulture. Social anthropology and

development in a south Indian livestock industry, New York.

Clarke, E., 2005: Ways of listening. An ecological approach to the perception of

musical meaning, Oxford.

De Hamel, C., 1992: Scribes and illuminators, London.
Eisenberg, L., 1972: The human nature of human nature, Science 176,

123–28.

Engelke, M., 2005: Sticky subjects and sticky objects. The substance of African

Christian healing, in D. Miller (ed.), Materiality, Durham, NC, 118–39.

Gell, A., 1998: Art and agency. An anthropological theory, Oxford.
Gibson, J.J., 1979: The ecological approach to visual perception, Boston.
Godelier, M., 1986: The mental and the material, London.
Gosden, C., 1999: Anthropology and archaeology. A changing relationship,

London.

Gran ¨o, J.G., 1929: Reine Geographie. Eine methodologische Studie beleuchtet

mit Beispielen aus Finnland und Estland, Helsinki.

Gran ¨o, J.G., 1997: Pure geography, in O. Gran ¨o and A. Paasi (eds), Pure

geography, Baltimore and London, 1–191.

Graves-Brown, P.M. (ed.), 2000: Matter, materiality and modern culture,

London.

H ¨agerstrand, T., 1991: Tidsgeografi, in B. Sollbe and G. Carlestam (eds), Om

tidens vidd och tingens ordning. Texter av Torsten H ¨agerstrand, Stockholm,
133–42

Hetherington, K., 2003: Spatial textures. Place, touch, and praesentia,

Environment and planning A 35, 1933–44.

Hodges, H., 1964: Artefacts. An introduction to early materials and technology,

London.

Horst, H., and D. Miller, 2006: The cell phone. An anthropology of

communication, Oxford.

Ingold, T., 1992: Culture and the perception of the environment, in E. Croll

and D. Parkin (eds), Bush base: forest farm. Culture, environment and
development
, London, 39–56.

Ingold, T., 1994: Humanity and animality, in T. Ingold (ed.), Companion

encyclopedia of anthropology. Humanity, culture and social life, London,
14–32.

Ingold, T., 1997: Life beyond the edge of nature? Or, the mirage of society, in

J.D. Greenwood (ed.), The mark of the social. Discovery or invention?,
Lanham, MD, 231–52.

Ingold, T., 2000: Making culture and weaving the world, in P.M. Graves-Brown

(ed.), Matter, materiality and modern culture, London, 50–71.

Ingold, T., 2005a: The eye of the storm. Visual perception and the weather,

Visual studies 20(2), 97–104.

Ingold, T., 2005b: Landscape lives, but archaeology turns to stone, Norwegian

archaeological review 38(2), 122–26.

Ingold, T., 2006: Rethinking the animate, re-animating thought, Ethnos 71(1),

9–20.

Ingold, T., 2007: Earth, sky, wind and weather, Journal of the Royal

Anthropological Institute, NS, S19–S38.

Keane, W., 2005: Signs are not the garb of meaning. On the social analysis of

material things, in D. Miller (ed.), Materiality, Durham, NC, 182–205.

background image

http://journals.cambridge.org

Downloaded: 10 Nov 2010

IP address: 143.167.2.135

38

discussion

Latour, B., 1996: ‘Lettre `a mon ami Pierre sur l’anthropologie sym´etrique’.

Culture mat´erielle et modernit´e, Ethnologie franc¸aise 26(1), 32–37.

Lemonnier, P., 1996: ‘Et pourtant c¸a vole! L’Ethnologie des techniques et les

objets industriels’, Culture mat´erielle et modernit´e, Ethnologie franc¸aise
26(1), 17–31.

Marx, K., 1930: Capital, Vol. 1 (tr. E. and C. Paul from 4th German edition of

Das Kapital (1890)), London.

Miller, D., 1987: Material culture and mass consumption, Oxford.
Miller, D. (ed.), 1995: Acknowledging consumption. London.
Miller, D. (ed.), 1998a: Material cultures. Why some things matter, London.
Miller, D., 1998b: Why some things matter, in D. Miller (ed.), Material cultures.

Why some things matter, London, 3–20.

Miller, D. (ed.), 2005: Materiality, Durham, NC.
Mulligan, H., 1997: Cave shelter, in P. Oliver (ed.), Encyclopedia of vernacular

architecture of the world, Vol. 1, Cambridge, 238–40.

Nilsson, B., 2003: Tingens och tankarnas landskap. F ¨ors ¨ok i naturumg ¨angets

arkeologi med exempel ur Blekinges och Sm ˚alands f ¨orflutna, Lund (Acta
Archaeologica Lundensia Series in 8

No. 44).

Olsen, B., 2003: Material culture after text. Re-membering things, Norwegian

archaeological review 36(2), 87–104.

Pelegrin, J., 1993: A framework for analysing prehistoric stone tool manufacture

and a tentative application to some early stone industries, in A. Berthelet and
J. Chavaillon (eds), The use of tools by humans and non-human primates,
Oxford, 302–14.

Pels, P., 1998: The spirit of matter. On fetish, rarity, fact, and fancy, in P. Spyer

(ed.), Border fetishisms. Material objects in unstable spaces, London, 91–121.

Pye, D., 1968: The nature and art of workmanship, Cambridge.
Renfrew, C., 2001: Symbol before concept. Material engagement and the early

development of society, in I. Hodder (ed.), Archaeological theory today,
Cambridge, 122–40.

Sollbe, B., 1991: Professorn fr ˚an Moheda, in B. Sollbe and G. Carlestam (eds),

Om tidens vidd och tingens ordning. Texter av Torsten H ¨agerstrand,
Stockholm, 203–19.

Tilley, C., 1999: Metaphor and material culture, Oxford.
Tilley, C., 2004: The materiality of stone, Oxford.
Toren, C., 1999: Mind, materiality and history, London.
Warner, M., 1996: Forms into time. The works of David Nash, in David Nash.

Forms into time, London.

Windsor, W.L., 2004: An ecological approach to semiotics, Journal for the

theory of social behaviour 34(2), 179–98.


Wyszukiwarka

Podobne podstrony:
Glucocorticoids alter fever and IL 6 responses to psychological
planning guidance for response to nuclear detonation 2 edition final
Kopelmann, Rosette Cultural variation in response to strategic emotions
Critical Responses to?scartes Skeptical Argument
No pain, no gain Masochism as a response to early trauma and implications for therapy
0811127 NR 653 ISAF quick reaction force responds to IED attack doc
CIA Responds to FOIA Snowden Documents
0415964903 Routledge DEMOCRATIC RESPONSES TO TERRORISM Dec 2007
Verizon Response to 9 11 9 11 Commish Interview
Dennett s response to Bennett and Hacker s Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience
An Analytical Extension of the Critical Energy Criterion Used to Predict Bare Explosive Response to
David Icke Responds To Charges In Canada
0415471958 Routledge The Psychology of Strategic Terrorism Public and Government Responses to Attack
The Legislative Response to the Evolution of Computer Viruses
15 How to Respond to Testing
DIA Responds to FOIA for Snowden Documents
Deloria, Response to David Brumble (1998)

więcej podobnych podstron