Plato's Early Dialogues
EUTHYPHRO
Persons of the Dialogue: Socrates and Euthyphro
Scene: The Porch of the King Archon
SUMMARY
As the dialogue begins, Socrates is on his way to court to face the
charges brought on him. Euthyphro is on his way to the court to prosecute
his
father for murder. Socrates is very surprised at Euthyphros
charge
against
his father and asks him if he is sure that what he is doing is pious
or
holy. He asks Euthyphro to tell him about the nature of piety and
impiety.
Euthyphro will not define piety or impiety, but instead says
Piety is doing as I am doing," and compares it with the actions of the god
Zeus when he punished his own father. Socrates asks for a definition and
not an example, to which Euthyphro offers that Piety is that which is dear
to the gods." Socrates accepts this definition, but forces Euthyphro to
admit that the gods differ, just like human beings, about what they love
and hate. By this definition, the same act may be called both pious and
impious, therefore this definition leads to contradiction. Euthyphro offers
a third definition and claims: What all the gods love is pious." Socrates
then asks whether an act is loved by the gods because it is pious, or and
act is pious because it is loved by the gods. Euthyphro responds that the
gods love an act because it is pious. By this, Socrates concludes that
Euthyphros
definition is only a characteristic of piety, not its definition.
At
this point, Euthyphro says that he does not know how to express what
he
means and accuses Socrates of setting arguments in motion. Socrates
is
not satisfied and accuses Euthyphro of being lazy, and forces the
argument
further by asking whether piety is a part of justice, or justice a
part
of piety. Here, Euthyphro offers yet another definition: Piety...is
that
part of justice which attends to the gods." Now Socrates wants an
explanation of attention," and asks if the gods benefit from this
attention," to which Euthyphro responds that the attention is like
ministration to the gods. Socrates then points out that ministration usually
means assisting someone in his work, and asks what ministration to the
gods helps them to do. Euthyphro responds that the discussion has
become tiresome, and issues his fifth definition: Piety...is learning how to
please the gods by prayers and sacrifices." Socrates asks if piety is an art
which gods and human beings have of doing business with one another,
and what benefits do the gods receive from the offerings of individuals.
Euthyphro answers that they get tributes of honour; they are pleased,
not benefited. Socrates tells him that by saying that the gods are pleased,
they have returned to an earlier definition. Frustrated and annoyed,
Euthyphro tells Socrates that he is in a hurry to depart and ends the
discussion.
ANALYSIS
This dialogue explores the meaning of Piety. As the dialogue starts,
Socrates is on his way to court to defend himself against accusations of
impious behavior; Euthyphro is prosecuting his own father based on his
own understanding in the matter of piety. As the dialogue develops,
Euthyphro
seems to take on the role of Meletus, Socrates
accuser. He
claims
to have perfect understanding in the matter of piety, so Socrates
requests
his help to answer Meletus charges against him. He asks
Euthyphro
to instruct him about the nature of piety. In his first definition,
Euthyphro
states that he is justified on bringing charges against his father
because
Zeus has done the same, and therefore there is divine
justification.
Later, Euthyphro offers other definitions about the nature of
piety,
and in all of them he implies that his knowledge in the subject is
indeed
superior to the majority. If this is the case, then only Euthyphro
is
the
judge as to whether an action should or should not be performed. He
starts
by justifying his actions through divine understanding, but Socrates
is
not satisfied. He then tries to make his actions right, but, again,
Socrates
leads him into contractions. Finally, he tries to turn his actions
into
a duty. Through the dialogue, Euthyphro tries to use the gods to
justify
his actions and interests, which is exactly the same charge that will
later
send Socrates to his death. When asked about the relationship
between
the gods and human beings, Euthyphro tells us that our duty is to
please
the gods and, through our actions, to honor and glorify them. If
this
is true, then we are nothing more than servants of the gods, crated
solely
to take them higher and higher. I hope our mission is somewhat
more
substantial than this. The dialogue does not offer an answer to the
question
of whether something is pious because is loved by the gods, or
something
is loved by the gods because is pious. Even if we were to
assume
that the gods love that which is pious, then love is only a
consequence
of a pious act. They both agree that piety implies justice,
but
justice does not imply piety. Thus, we can understand justice
without
bringing
in the matter of the gods, which seems to be the biggest problem
in
this dialogue. If we were to tie justice with the divine, this would
imply
that
reason alone would not be enough to define justice, but we would
need
divine guidance to do so.
Through
this dialogue, Euthyphro gets angry and frustrated; while
Socrates
tone is ironic and condescending. Euthyphro accuses Socrates
of
creating moving
arguments, but Socrates shows Euthyphro that his
argument not only moves around, but comes full circle to the starting
point. The dialogue shows us that if we are committed to the pursuit of
knowledge and truth, we must understand that this may be a never ending
process while we are in this life. Although our actions are based on our
limited knowledge, justice should always be an integral part of everything
we do.
APOLOGY
SUMMARY
The
Apology is Socrates
defense at his trial. As the dialogue begins,
Socrates
notes that his accusers have cautioned the jury against Socrates
eloquence,
but, according to Socrates, the difference between him and his
accusers
is that Socrates speaks the truth. Socrates distinguished two
groups
of accusers: the earlier and the later accusers. The earlier group is
the
hardest to defend against, since they do not appear in court. He is
also
accused of being a Sophist: that he is a teacher and takes money for
his
teaching. He attempts to explain why he has attracted such a
reputation.
The oracle was asked if anyone was wiser than Socrates. The
answer
was no, there was no man wiser. Socrates cannot believe this
oracle,
so he sets out to disprove it by finding someone who is wiser. He
goes
to a politician, who is thought wise by himself and others. Socrates
does
not think this man to be wise and tells him so. As a consequence,
the
politician hated Socrates, as did others who heard the questioning.
"I
am
better off, because while he knows nothing but thinks that he knows,
I
neither
know nor think that I know" (Socrates). He questioned
politicians,
poets,
and artisans. He finds that the poets do not write from wisdom, but
by
genius and inspiration.
Meletus
charges Socrates with being "a doer of evil, and corruptor of
the
youth,
and he does not believe in the gods of the State, and has other new
divinities
of his own." In his examination of Meletus, Socrates makes three
main
points: 1) Meletus has accused Socrates of being the only corruptor,
while
everyone else improves the youth. Socrates then uses an analogy: a
horse
trainer is to horses as an improver is to the youth. The point is
that
there
is only one improver, not many. 2) If Socrates corrupts the youth,
either
it is intentional or unintentional. No one would corrupt his neighbor
intentionally,
because he would harm himself in the process. If the
corruption
was unintentional, then the court is not the place to resolve the
problem.
The other possibility is that he does not corrupt them at all. 3) In
frustration,
Meletus accuses Socrates of being "a complete atheist," at
the
same
time he claims Socrates teaches new gods. Thus, Meletus
contradicts
himself.
Socrates
argues that fear of death is foolish, because it is not known if
death
is a good or an evil, thus there is no reason to fear death..
Socrates
claims
that his mission is in service to God. This is to condemn peoples
pursuit
of money, honor, and reputation, while ignoring wisdom, truth, and
the
improvement of the soul. When talking about politicians, he states
that
he
was a Senator once, and opposed the majority when several generals
were
brought to trial. He points out that several of the "corrupted
youth"
and
their fathers were present, but none of them were accusing him;
rather,
they were there in his defense.
Socrates
refuses to ask for pity. He does not throw himself on the mercy
of
the court. Many would bring in their children to win pity. However,
he
does
mention that he has three young children. He tells the jury about
their
responsibility
to ignore the appeals to pity and judge the truth.
Despite
Socrates speech, the jury finds him guilty as charged. Meletus
proposes
death as punishment. Instead, Socrates proposes retirement in
a
home for benefactors of the state. He examines possible penalties:
death,
imprisonment, a fine, or exile. Then, he realizes that exile is not
an
option
since he believes that "The unexamined life is not worth
living." He
finally
proposes a fine of 30 minae, guaranteed by Crito, Plato, and
others.
The jury sentences him to death.
Socrates
remarks that his internal, guiding voice, which at times would
warn
him to refrain from certain actions, had not once interrupted his
actions
in his defense. He argues that death might be a good: either it is a
dreamless
sleep, or he will travel to the place of the dead where he can
question
anyone and not be executed for it. He states: "No evil can
happen
to a good man."
He
asks the jury to punish his sons, and provide guidance. If so, then
he
will
have received justice. "We go our ways: me to die, you to live;
only
God
knows which is better."
ANALYSIS
Throughout
the Apology, Socrates believes himself to be a teacher,"
though he does not say that of himself. He finds reputed wise men and
questions them. If Socrates finds that they believe themselves to be wiser
than they really are, he points out their mistake, thus educates them and
himself. This allows Socrates to learn when he finds other people who
know more about a subject than he. Socrates tells the judges that he will
not be found guilty because of evidence and testimony; if he is found
guilty, it will be because of the reputation that he has obtained. As
Socrates deals with the charges, he is constantly talking about himself. If
Socrates wanted to appease the judges so that he would not be found
guilty, he could have made up or omit the parts about himself that caused
so much trouble. The fact that Socrates knows that he is being persecuted
for who he is and that he honestly describes himself, shows that he is
staying true to himself and his beliefs through his trial. Through reason,
Socrates is constantly searching for the truth of what others think. When
Meletus accuses Socrates of not believing in any gods, Socrates then uses
reason to refute him. Socrates tells a story about an oracle, which he
states that he believes in, and says that since an oracle is a divine thing he
must believe in divinities. Socrates used reason to question Meletus and
led him to state inconsistent statements: (1) Socrates corrupts the youth
intentionally. (2) Nobody intentionally harms himself. (3) People who
corrupt society ultimately harm themselves. If (1) Socrates corrupts the
youth intentionally and (3) people who corrupt society ultimately harm
themselves, then (2) must be false. However, if (2) nobody intentionally
harms themselves and (3) people who corrupt society ultimately harm
themselves is true, then (1) must be false (since Socrates cannot be
corrupting the youth intentionally). If that is the case, then the court is not
the proper place to discuss it.
The second section of the Apology is the speech that Socrates gives after
he is found guilty. In this speech, he is to propose a penalty for his
crimes." Socrates gives, at first, what he believes that he should receive
for his the actions, and he proposes that he should receive free room and
board. This remark shows Socrates still believes in his mission. Had he
proposed anything else, it would have been to indirectly admit that his
beliefs were wrong. For punishment, Socrates explores the idea of exile.
However, Socrates admits that, if exiled, he would continue to question
men about themselves. Socrates could have escaped death here by
submitting to exile and promising to change his ways, yet again, that
would undermine his beliefs. He then proposes a fine. In all the
punishments that he proposes, he never admits to being wrong or
promises to reconsider his ideas. Had he agreed to exile and silence, he
would not have stayed true to himself and his beliefs.
Socrates
philosophy of using reason to find the truth prevents him from
telling
the jury what they would like to hear. Each time Socrates proposes
a
punishment, he reasons himself out of it and into a worse punishment.
The
last section of the Apology deals with Socrates speech after he has
been
sentenced to death. Though Socrates becomes indignant, he does
not
become angry. Socrates does not do any of the weeping
and
wailing...[or the] many other things which [he] maintains are unworthy of
[himself]. Socrates believes that if he did, it would bring shame on
himself and his beliefs and that it would be much worse than death.
Socrates claims that he, unlike many others who appear before the jury,
will not appeal to their pity by having his family brought before them.
However, he does describe his family in some detail -- including his
sons. Here, he seems to be appealing to pity in a very subtle way.
Speaking about his children, he asks the jury punish them...if they seem
to care about riches or anything, more than about virtue; or if they...are
something when they are really nothing. Once again, he seems to be
instructing or teaching the jury about his beliefs. Socrates uses reason,
once again, to convince himself that death is not an evil. ...the state of
death is one of two things: either a dead man wholly ceases to be and
loses all consciousness or, as we are told, it is a change and a migration of
the soul to another place. Socrates goes on to say that, since neither of
those
two states of being can be bad, death shouldnt
be feared. His
philosophy
of reason allows him to look at death in a way that he does
not
have to be afraid of it.
Socrates
believes in holding on to his principle regardless of the
consequences,
even if they involve death. Concern for himself is not
nearly
as important as the pursuit of the good, the true, and the just. As a
result,
it is far better to suffer injustice than, through ignorance, to
cause it.
Justice
seems to be the prevalent theme, since this dialogue deals with the
injustice
against Socrates.
One
inconsistency is that in Crito he seemed universally opposed to
violating
the law, while in the Apology there seem to be exceptions to this
belief.
For example, he opposed the government actions (the law of the
State)
on two occasions.
The
speech that Socrates gives reflects the indignation he feels over
injustice
that he has received. However, a theme of courage in the face of
death
seems to be emphasized. Also, the point about staying true to
oneself
and beliefs, and the search for truth by way of reason is a policy
we
should all adopt.
CRITO
Persons
of the Dialogue: Socrates and Crito
Scene:
The Prison of Socrates
SUMMARY
This
dialogue takes place in the jail where Socrates awaits execution.
The
dialogue is a debate between Socrates and Crito about whether
Socrates
should escape. As the dialogue opens, Crito has arrived at the
prison
before dawn and sits by the bedside of Socrates, still asleep.
When
Socrates awakens, he tells Crito of a dream he has had. A woman
in
his dream implies that Socrates will soon find his home; death is
forthcoming.
Crito tells Socrates that he can use his influence and money
to
help Socrates escape. Crito is afraid that other people will think
he
should
have done more to save Socrates life. Socrates admonishes
Crito
no to value the opinion of the many, but of the few good men worth
considering.
Crito suggests Socrates is acting out of regard for him and
other
friends, and argues that Socrates is, en effect, committing suicide
and
betraying his children. Crito accuses Socrates of taking the easy
way
out
and tells him that others will think him cowardly if he does not
escape.
Socrates
counters that he cannot disobey the laws of Athens after Athens
has
granted him certain rights and has protected him. He cannot defy the
laws
for his own convenience. He argues that he cannot put away the
reasons
he has honored for 70 years, unless there is good reason to do
so.
Socrates claims that one should only regard the opinions of the
good,
not
the evil; he uses the analogy of the student of gymnastics that is
supposed
to listen to one man, and ignore the many; otherwise he will
harm
his body. The just man must only listen to the understanding;
otherwise,
he will harm his soul. Socrates says that first they must
determine
if escape is the right thing to do. If Crito can convince him, he
will
escape; otherwise, he will not. First, Socrates argues that one
should
never
do wrong intentionally, and return evil for evil, or wrong for wrong;
therefore,
just because the sentence is unjust, if escaping is wrong, he
must
remain in jail. Socrates imagines the government appearing before
him
to interrogate him. They charge him with overturning them, that a
State
cannot exist if the decisions of law have no power but are set aside
by
an individual. They talk about an agreement between him and the
State
to obey the laws, regardless of whether he receives justice or not.
Socrates
then compares the laws to ones parents. Just because a parent
strikes
a child, the child does not have the right to strike the parent.
Further,
he argues that the State is to be held higher and holier than
mother
or father. One must do what the State commands or change the
States
view of what is just. By remaining in the State, and existing under
its
laws, one enters into an implied contract to follow these laws for
three
reasons:
(1) in disobeying the laws, one is disobeying ones parents; (2)
the
State is the author of ones education; (3) one has made an
arrangement
with the State to obey its commands.
Socrates
could have had an agreement with the jury to fix the sentence at
banishment
but he said he preferred death to exile. Socrates tells Crito
not
to think of life and children first and of justice afterwards.
Socrates
then
asks Crito if he has any other argument to make. Crito responds
that
he does not. Socrates asks Crito to let him fulfill the will of God,
and
to
follow wherever he leads.
ANALYSIS
This
dialogue reflects Socrates teaching on moral obligation and duty.
Early
in the dialogue, Crito expresses admiration about the fact that
Socrates
is at peace about his coming execution. He accepts his fate.
When
discussing the opinions of others, Socrates uses argument
by
analogy," where he compares two things that are different on the surface
but, similar in some important areas. Socrates compares athletes who
care about improving their athletic performance with those who care
about the improvement of the soul. Socrates argues that he and Crito
must only listen to those who are knowledgeable about the issues at hand,
namely justice, fairness, and the ultimate good. Having established that
the good life is equal to a just and honorable life, the justice or injustice of
escaping
the laws
judgment is the only issue to be considered, and all of
Critos
personal arguments for escape are set aside. Socrates states that
making
a conscious choice to remain under the influence of a society, is
an
unconscious agreement with that society to live ones life by its
standards
and virtues. We see throughout the dialogue that Socrates
emphasizes
that the law should be either followed or challenged, but
never
ignored; on the other hand, his contempt for public opinion and
injustice
is evident. At the end of the dialogue Socrates states that, if he
refuses
to die, he will be disobeying the law; but it is not the law that is
unjust,
it is the men. Socrates reinforces the importance of respecting the
laws
as the foundation of society, otherwise our system of values and
justice
is subject to collapse.
PHAEDO
Persons
of the Dialogue: Socrates, Phaedo, Simmias, Cebes, Crito and
Apollodorus
Scene:
The Prison of Socrates
SUMMARY
The
dialogue is narrated by Phaedo to Echecrates, some time after
Socrates
death. The setting is early on the last morning of Socrates life.
Phaedo
lists those present, and notes that Plato was not there. Phaedo
makes
a point of describing Socrates attitude on this day: he appeared
calm
and fearless. When they have taken off Socrates chains, he remarks
that
pain and pleasure are two opposites that follow one another.
Cebes
notes that Evenus the poet had remarked at Socrates composing
poetry:
translating Aesop into verse, and composing a hymn to Apollo.
Socrates
explains that he has had a dream all his life to make
music
(poetry). Before, he had assumed that this meant his practice of
philosophy, but he wanted to be safe that it did not mean actual poetry.
Cebes asks why suicide is considered wrong. The implication is that
Socrates is too willing to die. Socrates argues that we are the possession
of the gods, so to kill ourselves would be to rob them. Socrates
expresses his belief that after death he will travel to the gods who are
good and wise, and will be in the company of others who are better than
those he will leave behind. Simmias asks Socrates to convince them, and
they will no longer charge him with suicide. Socrates claims that the
philosopher pursues death--the separation of soul and body, when the
soul exists in herself, and is parted from the body. Socrates argues that
the philosopher is unconcerned with pleasures of the body, that he would
rather turn completely to the soul. The philosopher, Socrates says, seeks
to sever the soul from the body. Socrates argues that when the soul
seeks truth, the body deceives it. Truth is revealed in thought, and thought
is best when the mind is gathered into herself. Socrates then introduces a
discussion of forms: absolutes of justice, beauty, and good. These, he
says, are not perceived with the bodily senses. Rather, these are
perceived with an intellectual vision, with the mind alone. The body, he
says, is a source of trouble that creates desires in us that keeps us from
seeking the truth. To attain pure knowledge, we must part from the body.
So after death, when the soul is alone and without the body, we may be
able to attain truth. So the philosopher seeks to separate the soul from the
body and enjoy a purification, and will leave this life with joy, and with no
fear of death. Cebes agrees with what Socrates has said, but asks how
we can know that the soul does not die with the body. Socrates begins
his response by mentioning the doctrine of reincarnation, that souls depart
at death to another world, and return, and are born from the dead. The
living comes from the dead, so the soul must be in another world.
Socrates supports this by discussing opposites, such as good and evil, hot
and cold, pain and pleasure, where one is generated out of its opposite.
In this way, life and death are opposite, and the process of life becoming
death is visible, but the process of death becoming life is not. Simmias
reminds
the group of one of Socrates
favorite doctrines, the Doctrine of
Recollection:
to learn something is actually remembering what has been
forgotten.
This would require the pre-existence of the soul in order to
have
the knowledge that is recollected in this life. Socrates supports
this
with
the example of equality: to judge two things as unequal, we must
first
know
what equality is; but we have no experience in this life of absolute
equality;
therefore, this knowledge must come from some previous
existence
in which the soul must have existed. This applies also to all the
other
absolutes, or forms. For all individual things we call by one name,
there
must be a single, essential nature which allows us to call them by
the
same
name. This essence is the form. This form is not visible, and is
never
seen
on earth. Nevertheless, we must use it as a standard by which we
judge
things to be what they are. Therefore, it comes from a
pre-existence
state when we were directly aware of them, and now we
recollect
them when we encounter things on earth that are copies of these
essences.
Cebes
repeats his objection that, even if the soul existed before birth, it
might
be destroyed at death. Socrates returns to the theory of forms, and
explains
that there are two sorts of existences, one seen, the other unseen.
The
seen is the changing, and the unseen is the unchanging. The body
belongs
to the visible and changing; the soul belongs to the invisible and
unchanging.
The philosopher seeks these unchanging forms and becomes
like
them. He is practicing death, or the separation of soul and body, and
is
purifying the soul of bodily elements that hold it down. Socrates
discusses
the souls or ghosts that linger around tombs, because they are
too
attached to the body. Then, Socrates states that if a person loves
the
body,
he becomes more like body, and this holds on to the soul after
death;
then, he will be reborn as a lower form of life. If a person loves
the
soul,
he becomes more like soul, and, the purified soul can escape after
death
and rise to the heavens.
Simmias
suggests that the soul and body are analogous to harmony and
the
lyre. Harmony is invisible, without body, and divine, while the lyre
is
visible,
material, and earthly. But when the lyre is broken, or the strings
cut,
the harmony dies. Thus, when the body is broken and dies, the soul
dies
too. Cebes offers another objection: he compares the soul to a coat
made
by a weaver. The weaver wears the coat until he dies, and then
someone
else wears it. The coat may outlast many men who wear it, but
finally
is worn out and dies. The same could apply to the soul; it may be
reborn
several times and outlast several bodies, but it will finally perish.
Socrates
argues that harmony is not like the soul. First, he reminds
Simmias
that he has already agreed that knowledge is recollection, and
that
the soul exists prior to this life. Therefore, the soul exists before
the
body.
However, the harmony of a lyre exists only after the existence of
the
lyre. Another difference between harmony and the soul is that the
lyre
causes
and controls the harmony. However, the soul is not led by the
body,
but the other way around. Also, Socrates argues that harmony has
degrees
and can be more or less harmonious. This is not the case with the
soul.
Socrates says that in order to refute Cebes objection, he will have
to
discuss the process of generation and corruption, which involves the
natural
sciences. He proceeds to scientifically explain the reason for his
sitting
in jail as the contraction of muscles and positioning of bones, but
the
real reason is that society has sentenced him to death, and he has
chosen
not to escape. Socrates again refers to the theory of forms as the
cause
of all things. Ideas exist and other things participate in them. For
example,
beautiful things come from absolute beauty. This hold for all
forms:
no opposites ever become mixed with each other (hot and cold,
life
and death). Socrates states that the soul is the creator of life and
it can
never
be mixed with death, which would be its opposite. Socrates then
stresses
the importance of taking good care of our soul at all times
because
of its immortality.
His
friends worry about the burial logistics as if the corpse they will
bury
is
Socrates. Socrates family returns. Once Socrates dismisses them, the
jailer
brings the poison. Cebes tells Socrates that there is still time to
enjoy.
However, Socrates thinks that there is nothing to be gained by
delay.
He drinks the poison and, following his jailers instructions, lies
down
when he feels his legs heavy. Socrates last words are to repay a
debt,
a sacrifice he owes to a god.
ANALYSIS
In
the Phaedo, we meet Socrates on the morning of his own execution.
Socrates
suggests philosophy and contemplation as a method to cast
away
the fear of death. He believes that the philosophical life is a
preparation
for death and that the true philosopher looks forward to
dying.
It seems that if philosophers look upon death with good
cheer,"
then they would not love life enough to learn and examine life and,
therefore, death. Socrates makes a distinction between two types of
death, figurative and literal, and defines death as the release of the soul
from the body. The responsibility of the philosopher is to seek the truth
and to prepare for the afterlife. Socrates notes that the body leads us
away from the truth. The discussion about the separation of body and
soul leads to the discussion of the immortality of the soul. Socrates
presents three arguments: one from the necessary generation of opposites
from opposi
Word Count: 5120